From: Rakesh Bhandari (bhandari@BERKELEY.EDU)
Date: Thu Mar 23 2006 - 04:01:47 EST
This is the html version of the file http://www.journalofcriticalrealism.org/archive/ALETHIAv3n2_dickens40.pdf. Peter Dickens Marx and the Metabolism between Humanity and Nature M ARX AND NATURE : a red and green perspective by Paul Burkett. St. Martinâ¤s Press, New York, 1999, viii, 312pp. ISBN 0-312-21940-7 (hbk only) MARX S E COLOGY materialism and nature by John Bellamy Foster. Monthly Review Press, New York, 2000, x, 310 pp. ISBN 1-58367-012-2 (pbk). Marxism, or historical materialism, has had a long-standing if sometimes problematic engagement with ecological issues. These two exceptional books take this association further. They resist inaccurate interpretations of Marx while locating his ecological thinking in its historical, philosoph- ical and theoretical contexts. Perhaps most importantly, they spell out new implications for present-day ecological understanding and politics. They suggest that much such understanding is narrow minded and insufficiently con- scious of the relations between internal and external nature. Over-industrialised readings of Marx Critiques of existing work start with what Burkett and Foster argue to be the currently over-industrialised under- standing of Marx. Perhaps the best known critique of Marx concerns his alleged Prometheanism. Marx, it is often argued, believed that capitalism had cracked the problem of natural resources. The problem of production had been solved, therefore a future communist society could assume there is no longer a problem of scarce resources. The cen- tral questions are thereby the reorganisation of capitalist social relations and the allocation of goods and resources more equitably. Such a construction of Marxâ¤s thinking has, understandably, found little sympathy with the Green movement. Typically within environmental politics, modernity is the problem rather than the solution. Anyone claiming that a future communism need not be ecological- ly conscious can be dismissed as an uninformed and unre- deemable clown. But, these books ask, do these arguments really reflect Marxâ¤s understanding? A second, and closely related, critique concerns Marxâ¤s alleged class reductionism. If the transition to communism is to be effected by the working class, this would seem to leave little scope for the so-called new social movements; those based on, for example, gender, race or locality. Marxâ¤s supposed economism also therefore leaves an unbridgeable gap between the â¤old⤠and â¤new⤠forms of pol- itics, the latter including most forms of ecological politics. At best, such a position renders alliances between, say, ecofeminists and Marxists, whose politics remain overly restricted to the class struggle, very difficult. At worst, it dismisses struggles other than those of class as largely irrel- evant. Therefore anyone trying to subsume ecological pol- itics within a theory of class struggle is a Marxian dinosaur who richly deserves exposure to the forces of modernity (and postmodernity) and accelerated extinction. But, once more, Burkett and Foster suggest that class reductionism is far too simplistic a version of Marxâ¤s rich understanding. All such interpretations of Marx largely leave the eco- logical question as an add-on to the basic theory. The ques- tion therefore becomes how can we hang on to the key and underlying tenets of Marxism (especially those which locate environmental degradation in the context of class relations, commodity production and the self-alienation of the human species) while recognising the contributions from environmentalists, feminists and others? Another â¤add-on⤠in the recent eco-Marxist literature concerns the nature of capitalist contradiction. Oâ¤Connor (1991), for example, is well known for his argument that an ecologi- cal Marxism must recognise a â¤second contradictionâ¤, one largely unrecognised by Marx himself. The first contradic- tion, according to this view, is the familiar one of overpro- duction; capital is unable to realise the surplus value incor- porated into commodities due to labour being controlled to the extent that it cannot consume the commodities made for it by capital. This in turn is associated with the rise of credit structures, aggressive marketing, increased competi- tion in an attempt to overcome periodic â¤crises of realisa- tion⤠and, in due course, massive and climactic social upheaval. But, according to Oâ¤Connor, capital also contin- ually confronts the conditions necessary for its own repro- duction. At this point we meet the second contradiction. These conditions include the environment. Global warm- ing, resource depletion and environmental degradation undermine (almost literally) the very conditions necessary for capitalâ¤s continuing reproduction and growth. Such undermining typically takes the form of extra and continu- ally growing costs imposed on capital. Green realism Such, then, are the kinds of critique and developments of Marxism which feature in the â¤red-green⤠literature. Again, however, both Burkett and Foster argue that they are based largely on false premises. They strongly suggest that an understanding of the philosophical bases to Marx indicates that humanityâ¤s relation to nature was always central to the development of his thought, and indeed to that of Engels. In a sense both these writers always were â¤ecologistsâ¤, if not ecologists as we would now know them. Similarly, the particular way in which Marx envisaged social relations and social struggle necessitated a sensitivity to nature and to humanityâ¤s relations to nature. According to these texts, therefore, Marxâ¤s theory of social change and social strug- gle has no need of the environment as an optional add-on. 40 Page 2 It is already integral to the historical materialism original- ly propounded by Marx and Engels. Furthermore, Burkett and Foster show that in Marx there is the kernel of a theo- ry which can greatly improve on contemporary environ- mental analysis. It proposes that the relation between humanity and nature must be extended to incorporate human nature; how human beings change themselves in the process of understanding and using the powers of nature to make the things they want. More generally, these authors (and Burkett in particular) are arguing from a broadly realist perspective which implies that what look like problems requiring ecological increments to the basic theory are really problems stem- ming, or emergent, from a basic underlying tension in cap- italism itself. This is a system of production based on prof- it but providing for human and social requirements. Environmental crises and struggles of many and diverse kinds are therefore envisaged as manifestations of this basic tension. All this of course leaves the question whether such an underlying problematic is indeed the only and most fundamental underlying mechanism affecting all forms of struggle and politics in capitalist society. But before turning to this contentious matter we should outline what, according to these texts, were the key elements in the making of Marx and Engels⤠understanding of society and nature, and how these might be extended to understand contemporary social-cum-ecological questions. Marx and Engels vs. Malthus⤠â¤system of despair⤠Malthus of course argued that, left unchecked, populations tend to increase at a geometrical rate while food at best increases at an arithmetical rate. His position was an impor- tant source of Marx and Engels⤠stance regarding humanityâ¤s relation to the environment. Malthus was what Foster calls a â¤parsonian naturalistâ¤. That population should increase faster than food was preordained by the Supreme Being. It is a process that created in Malthus⤠words â¤partial evil⤠but an â¤overbalance of goodâ¤. In particular it inspired and generated greater effort to create improved levels of subsistence. The problems of resource scarcity is quite literally, then, an act of God. It brings a balance of benefits, not least a range of desir- able Christian values such as sexual abstinence. Unsurprisingly, Marx and Engels had little time for Malthus⤠population theory. Engels⤠Outline of a Critique of Political Economy and Marxâ¤s 1844 Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts were especially virulent. Not only was Malthus⤠theory little more than religious dogma wrapped in (empirically unproved) science, but it was, Marx and Engels argued, dogma attempting to justify emergent forms of property relations. Bourgeois society had separat- ed nature from society. On the one hand, a God-given â¤nature⤠was being created, one denuded of human beings, detached from human intervention and experience and made â¤an objective of huckstering⤠by a property-owning elite; this despite the fact that nature still depends on human beings for fertilisation and that human beings depend on nature for their material and spiritual existence. On the other hand, great masses of people were being concentrated in the great cities devoted to industrial production. In much the same way that â¤nature⤠was being intensively exploited by a few, humanity or human nature was being intensively exploited by the owners of the means of production in industry. Malthus⤠religious naturalism, according to Engels and Marx, was therefore little more than a camouflaging apology for these processes. It attempted to justify both these processes as somehow â¤naturalâ¤, the land and its pro- ductivity as sacrosanct and unimprovable, while humanity remains inevitably subject to vices and practices leading to its own misery. It was â¤the crudest most barbarous theory that ever existed, a system of despairâ¤. This is therefore one important stage in blowing away theological mysticism and its replacement with a historical materialism. Feuerbach and the theft of dead wood After finishing his doctoral thesis, Marx was forced to aban- don his academic career as a result of the Prussian authori- ties⤠virulent campaign against the radical Young Hegelians. He became editor of the Rheinische Zeitung, a major Rhineland paper, and wrote an article entitled Debates on the law on thefts of wood. According to Foster, this repre- sented â¤an intellectual turning point in his lifeâ¤. It was, Marx believed, â¤the really earthly question in all its life-sizeâ¤. Stealing dead wood might sound like a trivial issue, but in Prussia during this period five-sixths of all prosecutions were associated with this matter. A system of private prop- erty over land was being established and reinforced. The last rites of common peasant ownership were being performed and Marx was protecting the rights of the poor to collect wood for their most basic needs, especially shelter, cooking and food. It was at this stage that he realised that his lack of knowledge of political economy was â¤embarrassing⤠and needed serious and urgent attention. Feuerbach, especially his critique of Hegel and his par- ticular form of materialism, was crucial at this point. His naturalism made sense of the young Marxâ¤s attempted pro- tection of the peasants⤠attempts to gain access to the land. â¤Manâ¤, Feuerbach wrote, â¤belongs to the essence of Nature⤠and â¤Nature belongs to the essence of Man. Only by unit- ing man with nature can we conquer the supranaturalistic egoism of Christianity.⤠It is a short step from here to Marxâ¤s assertion in the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts that nature is â¤manâ¤s inorganic body⤠and that alienation under modern property relations consists of estrangement from nature, from the material basis on which human society makes itself. It is also a short step from Feuerbachâ¤s materialistic assertion that science and philos- ophy â¤must be grounded in nature⤠and Marxâ¤s early plea for â¤one scienceâ¤, spanning the natural and human realms. As is well known, Marx and Engels were later to reject Feuerbachâ¤s â¤contemplative⤠materialism, around the time of The German Ideology. Henceforth Feuerbachâ¤s â¤man⤠was to be replaced by â¤real historical man⤠and â¤nature⤠by â¤natural history.⤠But the effect of engaging with Feuerbach was to be long lasting. From here on both historically cre- ated â¤man⤠and â¤nature⤠were to be central to Marx and Engels⤠historical materialism. 41 Page 3 Darwin: â¤the basis in natural history for our view⤠Marx, less so Engels, was ambivalent about Darwin. Clearly Darwinâ¤s adoption of Malthus as part of his con- ceptual framework was anathema. And his transposition of English society on to nature was spotted and commented on by Marx in a letter to Engels: It is remarkable how Darwin rediscovers among the beasts and plants, the society of England with its division of labour, competition, opening up of new markets, â¤inventions⤠and the Malthusian â¤struggle for existence.⤠It is Hobbes⤠bellum contra omnes. On the other hand, the Darwinian theory of evolution (developing the materialism long linked to evolutionary ideas) was attractive to Marx, not least because it repre- sented, in Fosterâ¤s words, â¤the death of teleologyâ¤. Marx went so far as to say that Darwinâ¤s theory was â¤the basis in natural history for our viewâ¤. Quite what he meant by â¤the basis⤠is subject to debate. Foster argues that Capital makes clear what he meant: that labouring on nature to produce commodities is the way in which Marx was to extend Darwinism into the human social realm. To some extent we are engaged here in old and not always produc- tive debates about â¤what Marx really meantâ¤. Certainly, the later Marx of Capital did use Darwin as a â¤basis⤠in the way Foster argues. But equally it could be said that Marx was looking back to Feuerbach in making this remark; he was again envisaging a single science, one linking â¤philos- ophy⤠and the emergent physical and natural sciences. But what is more clear is that Marx continued to treat Darwin with some suspicion, despite his endorsement of him as â¤splendidâ¤. This hesitation over Darwin is particu- larly clear in the seemingly rather curious adoption of Tremaux by Marx and the correspondence between Marx and Engels over Tremauxâ¤s 1866 book, Origine et trans- formations de lâ¤homme et des autre etres. Tremaux argued that human evolution is patterned by conditions of geolog- ical succession and changing soil conditions. Marx believed Tremaux to be â¤a very significant advance over Darwin⤠(his emphasis). This view seems to have partly stemmed from Marxâ¤s belief that Tremauxâ¤s theory explained gaps in the paleontological record. It also reflects Marxâ¤s concern that species should not be seen as neces- sarily undergoing constant improvement. Tremaux himself resisted such an understanding, adopting the theory that species eventually â¤revert to typeâ¤. But Marxâ¤s short lived adoption of Tremaux (dismissed by Engels due to the many errors he claimed were in the book) seems also to have stemmed from the perspective outlined earlier. Evolution is in part a product of the causal powers and mechanisms of species. But on the other hand, they actively change their environment (including the conditions of the land) and this in turn changes them. Again, this is Feuerbach revisited. Feuerbachâ¤s influence would also account for Marxâ¤s enthusiastic support (though not one discussed by either Burkett or Foster) of Fraas, a mid-nineteenth century doctor, agricultural historian and philosopher. In 1868 Marx argued in another letter to Engels that Fraas was â¤a Darwinist before Darwin and admits even the species developing in historical timesâ¤. In 1847 Fraas had written Climate and Flora over Time: a contribution to the history of both. This now almost wholly neglected text argued that the avoidance of desertifi- cation requires active and conscious control. More contro- versially, and yet more importantly for an understanding of Marx, Fraas argued that environmental degradation leads to social and cultural degradation. The decline of Greek civil- isation was, he believed, partly a result of internal dissent and struggle. But it was also a product of deforestation, the destruction of rain and water cycles, the consequent warm- ing-up of the earth, the deterioration of the soil and period- ic devastating floods. All this, he suggested, was closely associated with a series of social and cultural changes. Albanians moved in to cope with the deteriorating physical conditions, in particular with the degraded agriculture left behind by the Greeks. Meanwhile, the original Greek popu- lations moved into more profitable areas of work such as trade and commerce but became steadily weakened by changes in vegetation and climate. They were therefore no longer physically or culturally nourished by the environ- ment they had originally developed and Greek culture there- by went into steady and terminal decline. These arguments, with their assertions of racial purities and impurities, contain more than a hint of racism. Similarly, Marxâ¤s assertion to Engels that the Albanian incursors were prone to â¤every sort of shameless lechery and rape⤠was a repeat of not only Fraas⤠social prejudices but those of many other writers at the time. But the key point here again is that Marx was trying to develop Darwinâ¤s way of thinking. He was once more insisting that, as human beings work on nature to produce the things they need, they change themselves culturally as well as physically. The work of Fraas, like that of Tremaux, seemed to be backing up such a position. Marxâ¤s adoption of both Tremaux and Fraas in his attempt to upgrade Darwin can now be seen as problematic in a number of ways. More positively, however, it can be seen as a precursor to those current versions of Darwinism and evo- lutionary thought which emphasise not only the organism but its reciprocal interactions with its environment (Lewontin 1982, Dickens 2000). People finish up making themselves in making their environment. Similarly, the environment is indeed actively made and is not, as Malthus argued, an eternally fixed and morality-enhancing quantity. Such a perspective can of course be asserted and developed without adopting stereotypes about â¤speciesâ¤, â¤racesâ¤, their supposed biologically inherited predispositions and whether they represent the peaks or troughs of civilisation. Epicurus: â¤nature never reduces anything to nothing⤠If Feuerbach and Darwin are amongst the most obvious influences on Marxâ¤s ecological materialism, a perhaps less well known figure in this context is Epicurus. Yet he emerges as central in Fosterâ¤s study. And, since he was the subject of Marxâ¤s 1841 doctoral thesis, he was central to Marx too. Epicurus was an Athenian who is now reckoned by some biologists to be the most important forerunner of 42 Page 4 modern science. Indeed it is only in recent years, and in particular with the discovery of remains of papyri found in Philodemus⤠library in Herculaneum, that the full worth of Epicurus has been established. This discovery also largely confirms Marxâ¤s early interpretation of Epicurus. A part of the Greek philosopherâ¤s output was dedicated to dismiss- ing religious and superstitious views of nature; preferring to see human and non-human life (and indeed human nature itself) as emergent from the earth and the organisa- tion of matter. He was a naturalist, a materialist and a real- ist. He was resolutely opposed to determinism. Indeed, in Marxâ¤s opinion he tended to err on the side of abstract pos- sibility and neglect necessity or what Foster calls â¤real⤠possibility. The materialism and atheist philosophy of Epicurus are set down in his great book, On Nature. Here he argues, for example, that from the outset we always have seeds directing us some towards these, some towards those, some towards these and those, actions and thoughts and characters, in greater and smaller numbers. Consequently that which we develop â¤" char- acteristics of this or that kind â¤" is at first absolutely up to us. Most importantly, Epicurus was a very early progenitor of ecological science. Around 300 BCE he envisaged in a remarkable way the principle of conservation and thermo- dynamics, arguing that â¤nothing is ever created by divine power out of nothing⤠and â¤nature never reduces anything to nothingâ¤. Furthermore, he can now be seen as an early â¤Darwinistâ¤; recognising evolutionary processes of varia- tion and the adaptation of species to their environment. Foster shows Epicurus to have been immensely influential on modern scientific thought, Kant, Hegel, Bacon, Newton and Darwin as well as Marx being amongst those owing him intellectual debts. Suffice to say here, however, that Marxâ¤s early engagement with Epicurus was not, as is sometimes suggested, an aberration. Epicurus, an early ecologist and evolutionist, was centrally implicated at a key moment in the making of Marxâ¤s thought. Stoffwechsel, the labour process and metabolic rift Such were some of the key ingredients in the making of both Marxâ¤s and Engels⤠ecologically based thought. How did these ingredients congeal in their social and political theory? Both Foster and Burkett convincingly show that the â¤metabolism between man and nature⤠was at the heart of Marxâ¤s thinking, both the Marx of the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts and the Marx of Capital. It was also key to Engels, who is often seen as more sensitive than Marx to ecological and environmental questions. Metabolism, or Stoffwechsel, refers to the material exchange or interaction between human beings and nature. Such an interaction is, as set out in Capital, â¤the everlasting nature-imposed condition of human existenceâ¤. Human beings throughout history have confronted the processes and powers of nature. And they have set about using their bodies, arms, legs, hands and mental capacities to use the powers and materials of nature to adapt nature to their own ends. Therefore all social formations have not only been faced with nature but they have actively engaged with it to create the things they want. But the key feature of Stoffwechsel is not simply the labour process inaugurated by â¤manâ¤. â¤Metabolism⤠simultaneously refers to the changes effected on her or himself (on, that is, her or his own nature) in the process of modifying natureâ¤s powers. This dialectical way of thinking is at the heart of Marxâ¤s conceptual framework. Yet it has been largely ignored by disciplines such as environmental philosophy and environ- mental sociology. Put another way, Marx and Engels are offering a postdisciplinary vision. The concept of â¤metabo- lism⤠immediately makes organised links between social theory and such sciences as physics and developmental biology. Similarly, coherent association is made between â¤sociologyâ¤, â¤the sociology of the environment⤠and â¤the sociology of healthâ¤. This is the emergent â¤one science⤠to which Marx alluded in the early Manuscripts. But Stoffwechsel and â¤metabolism⤠were, for Marx and Engels, more than just concepts. They were used, as Burkett and Foster show in detail, for an analytical and political pur- pose. Capitalismâ¤s plundering of labour-power via the industrial labour process is a central and well known feature of Capital. But its plundering of ecological systems is like- wise a central, but much less well known feature. The result is no less than a nineteenth century analysis of environmen- tal sustainability. Marx in particular developed the idea of a â¤rift⤠in the metabolic relation between humanity and nature that was an emergent feature of capitalist society. The ten- dency, under the capitalist version of Stoffwechsel, was therefore to violate the nature-imposed conditions of sus- tainability. As Marx put it, â¤capitalist production turns towards the land only after its influence has exhausted it and after it has devastated its natural qualitiesâ¤(cited in Foster, 163). Marx intensively studied the work of industrial chemists of his day such as Justus von Liebig and built their analysis into the heart of his work, including Capital itself. He, like Engels in The Housing Question, documented at great length the implications of large numbers of people liv- ing in towns and the systematic failure to recycle the nutri- ents that had been removed from the soil. Urban pollution and irrational sewerage systems were all part of the meta- bolic rift under industrial capitalism. In Capital III, Marx noted that: â¤In London...they can do nothing better with the excrement produced by 4.5 million people than pollute the Thames with it, at monstrous expenseâ¤. It is hardly fair, therefore, to caricature Marx as uneco- logical. The implications of Capital for the twenty-first cen- tury surely stare the contemporary reader in the face. Nevertheless, those recent commentators who have recog- nised and used Marxâ¤s concept of metabolism have para- doxically tended to over-emphasise the use and misuse of raw materials (Fischer-Kowalski 1997, Schandl and Schulz 2000). The other half of Stoffwechsel â¤" the transformation of internal nature and of human social relations in the process of exchange with external nature â¤" has gone largely missing. Important as the ecological half of Marxâ¤s equation has become, the impact on society and the subsumption of inter- nal nature can hardly be denied. It must be retained as a cen- tral component of â¤manâ¤s metabolism with natureâ¤. 43 Page 5 Making value under capitalism The culminating point in these two books comes with Burkettâ¤s argument that the making of value, and in par- ticular the making of exchange-value under capitalism, must form the centrepiece of the analysis and of the poli- tics stemming from the analysis. The making of value, and its subsumption of both internal and external nature, is therefore the core element in the wrecking of both inter- nal and external nature. And since the making of exchange value is at the heart of Capital, so the degrada- tion of the environment is also at its core. Value, with all its anti-ecological features, remains the active factor disrupting the co-evolution of society and nature due to its treatment of people and nature as merely disguised modes of value itself. (98) Value, under its specifically capitalist form, is a product of both nature and labour. However, as Burkett insists, it is â¤sim- ply the abstract social labour time objectified in commodities⤠(79). So, while nature contributes to value, it is only doing so insofar as it is contributing to commodity-producing labour. In this sense it is quite wrong of Marxâ¤s critics to suggest that he was â¤Promethean⤠in the simplistic sense of assuming that nature could be treated as a free resource. He is saying here no more than what capital actually does. It uses nature as a free resource in the making of value in commodity production in the exploitation of human labour. The key problem, again, is that in subsuming or appropriating both external and inter- nal nature, capital is testing both internal and external nature to their limits. Note, however, that even this process is con- tradictory. Capitalism, by releasing people and nature from feudal social relations, has certainly had positive outcomes insofar as it has allowed the development of people as a social and natural species. As such, it has made the conditions for a new kind of communist society. It is also unnecessary and somewhat misleading to sug- gest that a â¤second contradiction⤠(concerned with the social and environmental conditions for accumulation) needs to be clipped on to a first contradiction concerned with crises of overproduction. The two are, as Burkett in particular insists, locked together. The first contradiction is rooted in capitalâ¤s social and political power over labour. And this power is itself rooted in capitalâ¤s appropriation of natural and social conditions. Again, such is the way in which labour-power and the objectification of surplus- value into saleable use-values is effected. Hence, Oâ¤Connorâ¤s attempt to relegate capitalâ¤s socialisation of the conditions of production to a â¤second⤠cost-side con- tradiction is, according to Burkett, â¤implausibleâ¤(195). Beyond â¤new⤠vs. â¤old⤠social movements? A similar line of argument extends to the critique of the supposed class reductionism of Marxâ¤s politics. Free com- petition is restricting the development of producers and is meanwhile ruinous to the environment. To counter this process workers must, according to Marx, â¤associate among themselves ... in the form of combinationsâ¤. As Burkett in particular points out, â¤the associational impera- tive⤠is a key feature of Marxâ¤s understanding of the transi- tion to communism. The combination of workers currently forced on them by industrial labour and by their living con- ditions takes largely defensive forms. It must be replaced under communism by new forms of combination which go beyond the wage-labour relation and defend the principle of association as a key mechanism in making new condi- tions for the development of human beings. Furthermore, and most importantly, such associations would not be focused on industrial production alone. As Burkett puts it: the problems of working-class life increasingly call out for explicitly social solutions that directly conflict with the princi- ples of privately contracted wage labour and labour market competition.. (211) These social solutions must include connections between industrial workers and others to education, transportation, health care and, of course, natural conditions. In this way narrowly conceived and industrialist visions of a future communism are, according to Burkett, super- seded. Popular and self-activated struggles in such areas of culture and domestic life join industrially based politics, with the common and unifying theme of what Burkett calls â¤a reappropriation of the social conditions of productionâ¤. This seems at first like a reasonable rallying cry; an umbrel- la under which, for example, many of the diverse groups attacking the World Trade Organisation might feel com- fortable. It is also in line with the attacks made by such groups on existing environmental policy making. Market- based policy institutions, according to Burkett, validate all the anti-ecological characteristics of value and cap- ital, but their enforcement may also be contradicted by the power and influence of competing capitalists. (220). Burkettâ¤s reworking of Marx also reasonably accounts for such â¤associations of producers⤠as the vast number of small-scale â¤third sector⤠organisations such as Local Exchange Trading Systems (LETS) or self-build groups. These groups are small and hardly visible but, taken together, they represent just the kinds of resistance to which Burkett refers. They are actively making the new kinds of producer and associations of producers to which he refers. Indeed Marx seems to have prefigured just these kinds of associations. His description in Capital of how a future association of producers might operate reads remarkably like an account of systems used by LETS schemes and by increasingly co-ordinated relations between such schemes in many contemporary societies. The individual producer receives back from society â¤" after the deductions have been made â¤" exactly what he gives to it. What he has given to it is his individual amount of labour .... The indi- vidual labour time of the individual producer is the part of the social labour day contributed by him, his share in it. He receives a certificate from society that he has furnished such and such an amount of labour (after deducting his labour for the common fund), and with this certificate he draws from the social stock of means of consumption as much as the same amount of labour costs. The same amount of labour which he has given to society in one form, he receives back in another. (Cited in Burkett, 233) But what about the power relations and divisions of labour supporting racism, patriarchy and other forms of oppres- 44 Page 6 sion such as ageism? Is the fact that domestic labour remains unpaid in contemporary capitalism simply to be celebrated insofar as it has so far resisted commodifica- tion? Surely, many feminists and others will still argue, the picture is more complex and contradictory than this. The argument should still be questioned, not least because such unpaid work and human skills can easily join external nature as yet another â¤free⤠input, further reducing the cost of labour-power for capital. In short, it is still not clear that independent or at least partly autonomous sources of social power other than class are adequately dealt with in Burkettâ¤s revised form of historical materialism. In this sense his study may be accused of being still â¤industrialist⤠in outlook, despite pleas to the contrary. In his defence it might be argued that class relations, commodity produc- tion and the misuse of nature can equally well exist inde- pendently of racism, patriarchal gender relations and so on. A more positive reading of Burkett is, therefore, that his politics is looking to a time when these other forms of oppression have been largely dispensed with and when capitalism remains as the main social force to be resisted and changed. In this sense it can be seen as an emancipa- tory vision after all. The debates set off by both Burkett and Foster will no doubt continue. But these two books certainly establish that simply picking and choosing â¤ecological⤠remarks in Marx and Engels is no longer sufficient for the develop- ment of a historical materialist ecology. Such a practice vastly underestimates the original centrality of ecology to the whole of Marx and Engels⤠work. These texts have therefore permanently changed the landscape for those attempting to view the relation between society and nature through a historical materialist lens. References Dickens, Peter (2000) Social Darwinism: linking evolutionary thought to social theory. Buckingham, Open University Press. Fischer-Kowalski, Marina (1997) Societyâ¤s metabolism: on the childhood and adolescence of a rising conceptual star, in Redclift, M., Woodgate, G. The International Handbook of Environmental Sociology. Cheltenham, Elgar. Lewontin, R. (1982) Organism and environment, in Plotkin, H. (ed) Learning, Development and Culture. Chichester, Wiley. Marx, K. Economic and philosophical manuscripts, in L.Colletti (ed) Karl Marx. Early Writings.Harmondsworth, Penguin. Oâ¤Connor, James (1991) On the Two Contradictions of Capitalism. Capitalism, Nature, Socialism 2, 3, 107â¤"9. Schandl, Heinz, Schuz, Niels (2000) Using material flow accounting to operationalize the concept of societyâ¤s metabo- lism: a preliminary MFA for the United Kingdom for the peri- od 1937â¤"1997. ISER Working Paper Number 2000â¤"3. University of Essex, UK. 45 International Association for Critical Realism and the Department of Social Sciences, Roskilde University announce
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Fri Mar 24 2006 - 00:00:04 EST