Re Steve K's [5132] and Gary's [5134]: 1) Response to Steve: Thanks for your post. I think it serves as a good starting point for accessing which Marxist models or illustrations are actually dynamic models and which are non-linear and chaotic. I take it that you would agree that some dynamic models can be simply specified -- in fact, you have a whole category called "boring" dynamic theories. I don't think, though, whether a model is "boring" can serve as a test for whether it is valid and you never really explained what was wrong with "boring" models other than having the subjective characteristic of being boring. When we discuss dynamic non-linear models, I think we should also ask whether the axioms and assumptions of the model are consistent with modeling a dynamic non-linear process. E.g. I don't consider the axiom that a unit of abstract labour creates the same magnitude of value everywhere in the world during all periods of capitalist history to be consistent with the process of viewing the creation and distribution of value as a dynamic non-linear process. Instead, it is an axiom which might only have limited meaning in the context of comparative statics. Similarly, I think that the conservation of value axiom which has been taken by some to imply that value can only be redistributed and can not be destroyed except by use is not consistent with viewing value in a dynamic non-linear context. Rather, I believe that these assumptions and axioms are employed for the reason that they reduce the number of unknowns and make the math simpler. Yet, I believe there is an injustice to understanding the process itself *as a dynamic process* when such axioms are employed. 2) Response to Gary I was waiting for someone else before responding. But your post was either surprisingly uncontroversial or no one wants to touch it. I'll touch. If your basic point is that comparative statics has a legitimate place in political economy, including Marxist political economy, then I agree. If your related point is that all subjects need not employ dynamic and non-linear tools, then I also agree. Yet, this leaves the major question unanswered: when is it appropriate to employ comparative statics and when is dynamic non-linear modeling appropriate? > > We might begin with a point that I think every competent economist -- > > orthodox, marxian (all variants), sraffian, post keynesian, Austrian, > > whatever -- would accept: that a useful explanation of how a market > economy > > functions must eventually deal with issues that fall under the heading of > > dynamics. I think I agree with you, but for some of these schools they only give lip service to "eventually": when and where, in terms of the order of analysis and the order of presentation, that eventuality is supposed to happen is left open. Kind of like "Waiting for Gidot". > > Well, to the extent that he's saying that there are certain kinds of > > questions -- extremely important ones, I contend -- that aren't > susceptible > > of analysis within the traditional long-period comparative static > > framework, he's not saying anything that Smith, Ricardo, Sraffa, or > > Marshall and Pareto, for that matter, would deny. I've never understood > the > > position that one must take an either/or stance: comparative statics on > one > > side versus some version of dynamic analysis on the other. > > "Horses for courses", as they say. There are different types of questions > > in economics, and they frequently call for different methodologies. Again, this doesn't answer the question I pose above. Even if there are different horses for courses, one has to place the question of which horse to employ within the context of the subject matter, capitalism, where that mode of production is understood as a unity of many determinations and where those determinatioins must be explained in a layered and ordered way. Thus, some horses which may be of use when presenting the most abstract theory may have to be abandoned for other horses as the level of concretion advances. > > Questions relating to the fundamental mechanisms that operate on prices > and > > distribution, it seems to me, ought to be sorted out, in the first > > instance, via the traditional method. ("Traditional"? I'm not convinced that we ought to embrace the "tradition" of mainstream economic theory). Implied in your statement above is the proposition that prices and distribution are the "fundamental mechanisms" that have to first be explained at a very abstract level. On the contrary, I think that the category of price, as distinct from relative price, is a very complicated category that has to be understood at varying stages of the analysis. E.g. prices of production are not market prices and the order in which market prices, the more concrete category, should be introduced is after the more abstract category of POP. If we forget to do this consistently then we run the risk of collapsing a very rich and detailed and complex and layered analysis of the subject of capitalism to a much simpler yet inadequate theory that does not integrate and endogenize essential variables necessary for comprehending that subject matter. E.g. if our theory only understands money as numeraire, then our theory can not comprehend important aspects of the subject matter, e.g. credit money and fictitious capital. > > For a start, I don't see how technical change and transitional processes > > can be modeled without relying on suppositions that are much more ad hoc > > than what one finds in, say, Sraffa-type long-period models. I don't exactly understand *why* you "don't see" this. While I agree that one has to question the appropriateness of what you call "ad hoc" suppositions, I don't understand why the analysis of technical change *requires* such suppositions. > > The upshot is that for the anlysis of dynamic questions it might be more > > appropriate to adopt the approach of Adam Smith and Marx: look at history > > and institutions. By all means, supplement the history and institutional > > analyisis with formal dynamic models when the latter can shed light on > > complex processes that have a systematic dimension. But in the end, I > > think that formal modeling is less helpful to the analysis of capitalism's > > temporal trajectory than good old-fashioned in-the-trenches historical and > > institutional work. I agree that historical and institutional analysis, or what might be called "class studies", should form part of the analysis and presentation. Indeed, I think it can be *every bit* as empirical as statistical and econometric work (even though most economists don't weigh its worth as above). Indeed, I would especially argue that serious historical and institutional analysis is required rather than relying on pseudo-historic "stylized facts". > Isn't this what Marx was doing throughout most of > > Capital, and Smith was doing throughout most of the Wealth of Nations? I > > don't think the basic approach is outmoded. No, I don't think that was Marx's method. Certainly there is a lot of historical and institutional detail in _Capital_, but the method employed is one of abstraction which *presumes* a prior analysis of the concrete (so that the subject matter can be reconstructed in thought) rather than a historicist/institutionalist/ empiricist method. Indeed, I think that the historical detail could have been omitted from the main presentation and relegated to footnotes without doing his theory an injustice. On this matter listmember Tony Smith wrote that the distinction between "Denken" and "Vorstellung" is significant. "Vorstellung", Tony writes, may be translated as "picture-thinking" or "imaginary representation" (_The Logic of Marx's Capital: Replies to Hegelian Criticisms_, p,11). The historical details, thus, are presumed to be generally understood as a precondition for the reconstruction of the subject matter in thought, but are not necessary in terms of the actual presentation. Indeed, one might say that the historical presentation is "redundant". In solidarity, Jerry
This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Mon Apr 02 2001 - 09:57:28 EDT