[OPE-L:5189] Re: Re: use-value as qualitative

From: Steve Keen (s.keen@uws.edu.au)
Date: Fri Mar 16 2001 - 15:23:21 EST


A longer reply to Jerry's query:


>PS: In reply to Steve K's [5183-4] -- I view use-value
>>as quality, exchange-value as quantity, and value
>>as a unity of quality and quantity (this is why I
>>suggested at one point that use-value stands in
>>opposition to exchange-value -- a point Chris A
>>and I discussed last year).
>>
>>Thus, my perspective is that use-value is not
>>quantitative, BUT I am willing to listen to your
>>arguments as to why:
>>
>>a) you think this is a logical extension of Marx's
>>philosophy; and
>>
>>b) why you think it is a superior way of
>>conceptualizing use-value.
>>
>>I.e. I want to hear the arguments themselves rather
>>than the assertions.
There are several stages to a reply.

Taking Jerry's (a), I see two things I have to establish: (i) that the 
concept of a dialectical unity of use-value and exchange-value was an 
essential part of Marx's philosophy; (ii) that one key aspect of this was 
that, in important and clearly delineated circumstances, use-value was 
quantitative, not qualitative.

(i), I would hope, is incontrovertible since the publication of the 
Grundrisse (pardon me for not removing my DTP formatting codes as I 
normally do). I could grab hundreds of quotes, but two will do. Key phrases 
are highlighted with asterisks:

"We already saw, for example, that *the distinction
between use value and exchange value belongs within economics
itself, and that use value does not lie dead as a simple
presupposition, which is what Ricardo makes it do.* The chapter on
production begins objectively ends with the product as result;
that on circulation beginning with the <I>commodity<D>, which is
itself again a <I>use value<D> and an <I>exchange value<D> (hence
also, distinct from both, a <I>value<D>), circulation as the
unity of both <196> which is, however, merely formal and hence
collapses into the commodity as mere object of consumption,
extra-economic, and exchange value as independent
money.<170><$FIbid, p. 320.>

"The first category in which bourgeois wealth presents itself
is that of the <I>commodity<D>. The commodity itself appears as
unity of two aspects. It is <I>use value<D>, i.e. object of the
satisfaction of any system whatever of human needs. This is its
material side, which the most disparate epochs of production may
have in common, and whose examination therefore lies beyond
political economy. *Use value falls within the realm of political
economy as soon as it becomes modified by the modern relations of
production, or as it, in turn, intervenes to modify them.*<193>
Now how does use value become transformed into commodity? Vehicle
of <I>exchange value<D>. Although directly united in the
commodity, use value and exchange value just as directly split
apart. Not only does the exchange value not appear as determined
by the use value, but rather furthermore, the commodity only
becomes a commodity, only realises itself as exchange value, in
so far as its owner does not relate to it as use
value.<170><$FIbid, p. 881.>

The key detail is the role use-value plays in his analysis, and whether it 
is always qualitative, or can as I argue be quantitative. In the above 
quote, Marx distinguishes two possibilities for use-value: it can lie 
outside or inside the realm of political economy:

It is <I>use value<D>, i.e. object of the
satisfaction of any system whatever of human needs. This is its
material side, which the most disparate epochs of production may
have in common, and whose examination therefore lies beyond
political economy. Use value falls within the realm of political
economy as soon as it becomes modified by the modern relations of
production, or as it, in turn, intervenes to modify them.

The former aspect of use-value is clearly qualitative, and it is the aspect 
of use-value which most Marxists (Sweezy in particular) have focused on. 
However, the final sentence is crucial: "Use value falls within the realm 
of political economy as soon as it becomes modified by the modern relations 
of production, or as it, in turn, intervenes to modify them." I argue that, 
to "fall within the realm" of *Marx's* political economy, this aspect of 
use-value has to be quantitative. If Marx were a neoclassical, then it 
could of course be a qualitative concept. But since qualitative issues form 
no part of his core analysis (except when he reduces qualitative 
differences to quantitative ones, as in the reduction of skilled to 
unskilled labour--of which more later), to become an issue in Marx's 
political economy, use-value has to somehow in some circumstances be 
quantitative.

Now I need two arguments to support this: (i) a methodological one: in what 
circumstances does it make sense to describe use-value as quantitative? 
(ii) textual support that Marx in fact does this, in crucial ways.

The normal perspective on use-value comes from the sphere of circulation, 
C-M-C, where the purchaser is effectively swapping one commodity for 
another. The only reason to do this is to get rid of a (qualitative) 
use-value you don't want, in return for a (qualitative) use-value that you 
do need. Marx clearly states that use-value is qualitative in this realm:

"So far as regards use-values, it is
clear that both parties may gain some advantage. Both part with
goods that, as use values, are of no service to them, and receive
others that they can make use of" (Capital I 155).

Marx's special perspective on use-value arises from its role in the circuit 
of capital, M-C-M. Here he is quite emphatic that use-value *MUST* be the 
explanation of the source of surplus value. This can only occur if, in this 
realm, use-value is quantitative. Marx's statement on this issue is one of 
the clearest and most didactic he ever made, and for the life of me I still 
can't fathom how most Marxists fail to appreciate this. When discussing 
where the source of surplus value lies, having ruled out C-M-C, he 
discusses M-C-M, and quite clearly states that use-value holds the key to 
surplus value:

"The change of value that occurs in the case of money
intended to be converted into capital ... must ... take place
in the commodity bought by the first act, M-C, but not in its
value, for equivalents are exchanged, and the commodity is paid
for at its full value. We are, therefore, forced to the
conclusion that the change originates in the use-value, as such,
of the commodity, i.e. its consumption. In order to be able to
extract value from the consumption of a commodity, our friend,
Moneybags, must be so lucky as to find, within the sphere of
circulation, in the market, a commodity, whose use-value
possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value" (p. 164)

Marx continues "whose actual consumption, therefore, is itself an 
embodiment of labour, and consequently, a creation of value." I dispute 
this identification of labour as the sole source of value, of course; it 
appears that most readers of Marx focus on this aspect of this quote, 
rather than the definitive methodological statement which precedes it. I 
believe we should instead focus on the methodological argument for the 
derivation of surplus-value: "We are, therefore, forced to the conclusion 
that the change originates in the use-value, as such, of the commodity".

To cut to the chase, for M-C to generate surplus, the capitalist must be 
able to buy commodities which can generate more value than they cost to 
purchase. Production is an essential component of this, but what the 
capitalist exploits is the *quantitative* difference between the 
exchange-value of these commodities and their use-value. That such a 
difference can exist is an essential component of Marx's logic (especially 
in contrast to neoclassical economics):

"The exchange of commodities, therefore, first begins on the boundaries of 
such communities, at their points of contact with other similar 
communities, or with members of the latter. So soon, however, as products 
once become commodities in the external relations of a community, they 
also, by reaction, become so in its internal intercourse. The proportions 
in which they are exchangeable are at first quite a matter of chance. What 
makes them exchangeable is the mutual desire of their owners to alienate 
them. Meantime the need for foreign objects of utility gradually 
establishes itself. The constant repetition of exchange makes it a normal 
social act. In the course of time, therefore, some portion at least of the 
products of labour must be produced with a special view to exchange. From 
that moment the distinction becomes firmly
established between the utility of an object for the purposes of 
consumption, and its utility for the purposes of exchange. *Its use-value 
becomes distinguished from its exchange-value.* On the other hand, the 
quantitative proportion in which the articles are exchangeable, becomes 
dependent on their production itself." (Capital I, p. 91>

So the use-value and the exchange-value of a commodity in M-C-M will obey 
the general laws that "its use-value becomes distringuished from its 
exchange-value" and that value determines exchange-value wholly 
independently of use-value. Marx then uses this to derive the source of 
surplus value. The use-value of labor which he contemplates here is clearly 
quantitative:

The past labor that is embodied in the labor power, and the
living labor that it can call into action; the daily cost of
maintaining it, and its daily expenditure in work, are two
totally different things. *The former determines the
exchange-value of the labor power, the latter is its use-value.*
The fact that half a [working] day's labor is necessary to keep
the laborer alive during 24 hours, does not in any way prevent
him from working a whole day. Therefore, the value of labor
power, and the value which that labor power creates in the labor
process, are two entirely different magnitudes; and this
difference of the two values was what the capitalist had in
view, when he was purchasing the labor power... What really
influenced him was the specific use-value which this commodity
possesses of being a source not only of value, but of more value
than it has itself. This is the special service that the
capitalist expects from labor power, and in this transaction he
acts in accordance with the 'eternal laws' of the exchange of
commodities. *The seller of labor power, like the seller of any
other commodity, realizes its exchange-value, and parts with its
use-value.* (capital I, p. 188.)

To rearrange the above:

"The past labor that is embodied in the labor power, the daily cost of 
maintaining it, determines the exchange-value of the labor power; the 
living labor that it can call into action, its daily expenditure in work, 
is its use-value."

This use-value is clearly quantitative.

Finally, what I think should be accepted as the textual clincher:

"*Exchange-value and use-value, being intrinsically incommensurable
magnitudes*, the expressions <169>value of labour<170>, <169>price
of labour<170>, do not seem more irrational than the expressions
<169>value of cotton<170>, <169>price of cotton<170>. Moreover,
the labourer is paid after he has given his labour. In its
function as means of payment, money realises subbsequently the
value or price of the article supplied<196><I>i.e.<D>, in this
particular case, the value or price of the labour supplied.
Finally, the use-value supplied by the labourer to the capitalist
is not, in fact, his labour-power, but its function, some
definite useful labour, the work of tailoring, shoemaking,
spinning, &c. That this same labour is, on the other hand, the
universal value-creating element, and thus possesses a property
by which it differs from all other commodities, is beyond the
cogniscance of the ordinary mind.<193> Moreover, the actual
movement of wages presents phenomena which seem to prove that not
the value of labour-power is paid, but the value of its function,
of labour itself." (Capital I p. 506.)

Note the statement in asterisks: ""Exchange-value and use-value, being 
intrinsically incommensurable
MAGNITUDES." A magnitude is not qualitative: it is quantitative. This can't 
be treated as a slip of language or sloppy editing by Engels--this is in 
volume I, not III. That one sentence is the essence of what I see as Marx's 
theory of value: exchange-value, use-value, their incommensurability (in 
general, also applying of course when use-value is qualitative and 
therefore irrelevant to political economy), and that use-value is 
*quantitative* when it matters to political economy.

Now Jerry's final question:

>>b) why you think it is a superior way of
>>conceptualizing use-value.
Conceptualising use-value as purely qualitative means it has no role in 
economics. Some might argue that the reduction of skilled to unskilled 
labour, and specialised to homogeneous labour, involve economically 
significant applications of the qualitative side of use-value. There is 
some truth in that--but even here, as Hilferding showed in his reply to 
Bohm Bawerk, the quantitative side of use-value is decisive.

Going beyond this alone, the superiority of this way of conceptualising 
Marx's theory of value is that it allows a complex, subtle analysis which 
captures the unique aspects of labour, capital and money in a way which is 
simply beyond the LTV. I sit in amazement as I watch people try to develop 
a meaningful theory of money on the basis of the strictly 
commodity-oriented analysis of the LTV, when there is a much richer credit 
theory of money for the taking in terms of Marx's use-value/exchange-value 
analysis.

Of course, the real reason why I find myself alone in taking this approach 
to Marx is that it also leads to the argument that labour is not the only 
source of surplus value.

cheers,
Steve



This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Mon Apr 02 2001 - 09:57:29 EDT