Hi Rakesh, Thanks for your reply. I don't want to discuss the relative merits of bolshevism and council communism here, I am only exploring the concept of the Marxian law of value. I am very appreciative of Weeks's writings, but I have four objections to his interpretation of the law of value. A. Weeks is actually unable to specify unambiguously what the law of value means and shifts from one meaning to another. In his book Capital and Exploitation, he defines the law of value variously as: 1. The law of the minimization of abstract labour time (p. 33) 2. The 'law of socially necessary labour time' and the 'law of the tendency of the rate of profit to equalize'. (p. 40). 3. The law of the exchange of equivalent quantities of social labor, which "is in fact the law of surplus value - the law of the appropriation of unpaid labor (p. 40) 4. The law of labor time under capitalism (division of labor), the law of surplus value (exploitation), but also the mechanism of alienation (p.48-49) 5. A law of capitalist accumulation, not a natural law (p. 85) 6. The law of the exploitation of labor under capitalist social relations (p. 85) Now of course one could, like Alice in Wonderland, make words mean what one wants them to mean at any particular time, but then our argumentation is a tautology. In this case, the tautology is that the law of value is specific to the capitalist mode of production alone... because it is specific to the capitalist mode of production alone. Weeks' proof is just a matter of juggling terms. The consequence is that there is no adequate explanation of the historical origin of the law of value, and that the conditions for the withering away of the law of value cannot be specified adequately either. (B) Weeks caricatures Engels's position, by extracting quotes out of context. I don't have the time at the moment to lay all the texts side by side, but consider just one quote from the central essay by Engels which Weeks finds so objectionable, included as a supplement to Capital Vol 3: "If manufacture sprung ahead by cheapening its products, this is even more true of modern industry, which forces the production costs of commodities lower and lower through its repeated revolutions in production, relentlessly eliminating all former modes of production. Its is large-scale industry, too, that thus finally conquers the domestic market for capital, puts an end to smallscale production and natural economy of the self-sufficient peasant family, eliminates direct exchange between small producers, and places the entire nation in the service of capital. Likewise, it equalises the profit rate of the different commercial and industrial branches of business into one general rate of profit, and finally ensures industry the position of power due to it in this equalisation by eliminating most of the obstacles formerly hindering the transfer of capital from one branch to another. Thereby the conversion of values into production prices is accomplished for all exchange as a whole. THIS CONVERSION THEREFORE PROCEEDS ACCORDING TO OBJECTIVE LAWS, WITHOUT THE CONSCIOUSNESS OR THE INTENT OF THE PARTICIPANTS" (my emphasis, Capital Vol 3., Moscow ed., p. 906). In other words, the "subjective perception theory of labour-value" which Weeks ascribes to Engels doesn't do justice to what Engels means. What Engels means is that in pre-capitalist societies a lot of labour-accounting took place, people were well aware of the labour-time involved in producing products offered for exchange. Therefore under conditions of "simple exchange" or less developed exchange, they took this in consideration in pricing goods or determining the exchange ratios of goods. They were indeed forced to do this to survive, and the more dependent they became on exchange, the more it regulated their behaviour, regardless of the original subjective intentions. That is, briefly put, the historical origin of the economic category of abstract labour. Engels however does not say, as Weeks alleges, that "subjective perception of labour-time" is the way people go about exchanging in a full-fledged capitalist society (other than, perhaps, in the sense that capitalists carefully monitor labour-costs, and that workers compare labour-effort to the wages they receive and to the price of goods they buy). His point is rather that with the growth of the capital and commodity market, the law of value increasingly asserts itself regardless of subjective valuations, in the specific way that Marx describes. In Weeks's own interpretation, you just "suddenly" have abstract labour when you have capitalism, he ignores the historical process by which the abstraction of labour occurs through the emergence, growth and increasing sophistication of trade in commodities. C. What Marx and Engels meant by the law of value is quite simply that, other things being equal, the value of commodities being exchanged is determined by the average labour-time socially necessary for their production (assuming equal exchange). A simple statement of the law of value in this sense was already provided by David Ricardo at the very beginning of the first chapter of The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation (although Ricardo doesn't use the expression "law of value"): "The value of a commodity, or the quantity of any other commodity for which it will exchange, depends on the relative quantity of labour which is necessary for its production, and not on the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour". In his famous letter to Kugelmann of 11 July 1868, Marx does not object to this idea as such (which, as he says, is quite a lot older than Ricardo), but rather that Ricardo assumes that which has to be explained: "Science consists precisely in demonstrating HOW THE LAW OF VALUE ASSERTS ITSELF (my emphasis). So that if one wanted at the very beginning to "explain" all the phenomena which seemingly contradict that law, one would have to present science before science. It is precisely Ricardo's mistake that in his first chapter on value he takes as given all possible and still to be developed categories in order to prove their conformity with the law of value". The root of Ricardo's error is his ahistorical approach. So the determination of commodity values by labour-time is indeed thousands of years old, as Engels says, and in his book Capital Marx indeed painstakingly traces out the forms of exchange-value from the elementary to the general forms, insisting the substance of value is labour. But that does not mean that the law of value asserts itself IN THE SAME WAY under conditions of partial (simple) commodity production and generalised commodity production (capitalism). The law of value asserts itself in a different way under capitalism precisely because it is "production of commodities by means of commodities", which means inter alia the formation of production prices and market values. So the story of the evolution of the law of value is a question of tracing out the development of trade, showing how the growth of trade gradually dissolves primitive communities and forms a national and international market, and how it gradually engulfs the entire production process of society. D. Because of Weeks's definition of the law of value, he is unable to give an adequate critique of Stalin's views of the law of value under socialism. Weeks says that Stalin confuses the law of value with the necessity for allocating labour-time, but that is not the case. Stalin says explicitly that the law of value applies only to commodity production, which was partially superseded in the USSR. Stalin was not wrong in saying that the law of value "influences production" in the USSR, to the extent that you had a market for consumer goods, faced pressures of the world market to an extent, and remunerated labour through wages which were related to labour effort. Rather the problem is that Stalin believed that the USSR was genuinely socialist, and that the law of value does operate in a socialist economy. That is, Stalin's concept of socialism was at variance with Marx's idea of socialism as a marketless and classless society in which labour is no longer dominated by commercial forms, and Stalin had no adequate program for the supersession of market relations, through a different set of institutions for the production and distribution of goods and services. Regards Jurriaan CC. Paul Bullock Paul Cockshott
This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Sat Aug 24 2002 - 00:00:03 EDT