People are probably aware that Alfredo SF has a book out (The Value of Marx: Routledge). This has the merit of treating value-form theory as of major importance among current trends; but the treatment is a little cursory (pp. 26-29). Nonetheless, I think it is illuminating to discuss the issues raised: so here goes with a first installment. One of the difficulties Alfredo, or anyone else, faces is that VF theorists share only a family resemblance; there are different versions; here naturally I speak largely for myself. In order to simplify his task Alfredo takes I. Rubin as paradigmatic, even though references in the notes show his familiarities with current VFT. But although Rubin is an important predecessor it does not follow that criticisms of him disposes of current VFT. But he simply takes Rubin as the gold standard and thinks if he refutes Rubin he has refuted the whole school. But this is not true. There are three major problems about value of which R dealt only with one (and because of this distorted even that); these are the nature of the form assumed by the product; the necessity of money; the form determination of production. R deals with how the product of labour becomes a value; here he says some correct things about abstract labour in polemicising against 'labour-embodied' interpretations and insisting on the social determination of AL ('This equalisation of labour may take place, but only mentally and anticipated, in the process of production. But in reality it takes place through the act of exchange through the equalisation of the product with a definite sum of money.' p.142); but he fails completely to deal with the development of the value form to money, which of course is a key thing for all of us; still worse he thinks that value and abstract labour are real only at the moment of exchange, as the above passage indicates. Alfredo moans about this but he does not tell people that Reuten and Williams start from production, and that I have made very clear, e.g. in my C&C 73 (2001) piece, that the VF must penetrate production such that it too is value in motion, and that 'abstract labour' has a reality at the level of the capital relation. ALfredo likes that piece but does not notice it is relevant when he thinks he has refuted VF theory. Central to Alfredo's critique is that VFT wrongly prioritises the private over the social. He crits Rubin because the stress on the social form of exchange goes along with a relative neglect of that other key social form, the capital relation. This leads to a somewhat misleading characterisation of production as 'private' as if it were like simple commodity production. But it is clear VF can extend its form approach to the capitalist factory (R&W start there, and see my piece in C&C). The circuit of capital includes the production process, as a movement 'of' value, not just 'for' value. Hence abstract labour exists in the factory. Alf rightly says that VFT 'starts from the social division of labour' (26) but then very curiously has a criticism that 'focus on the value relation implies that ... producers do not belong to the social division of labour'. (27) He goes on to say that because the theory stresses 'separation' it assumes 'production is essentially for consumption, and private and concrete labour is analytically prior to social and abstract labour which exist only ideally before sale.' (27). Let us try to sort this out. Following R&W let us consider sociation, dissociation ; and association. By sociation is meant the universal, ahistorical reality that in order to be active economically, people engage in social relationships and social practices. Outside of a Robinson Crusoe situation, production and consumption are immediately, or mediatedly, socially contextualised. By dissociation (the negation of sociation) is meant the historically specific reality of the separation between economic agents predominant in the bourgeois epoch; 'separation' here does not mean a geographical distance of course, but a social barrier. Dissociation has three dimensions: first that useful objects are held by persons as their private property and hence are not immediately available for satisfying the needs of others; second that production is carried out in enterprises likewise in the hands of private owners; third that labour-power is separated from its object in that the most important means of production are held as the property of members of the capitalist class. By association is meant that the opposition of sociation and dissociation is mediated in the form of exchange whereby consumers acquire the objects they require, production units acquire inputs and dispose of outputs, and through contracts of labour people find work and capitalist enterprises find workers. It is important to understand that when dissociation is negated through association this is on the same ground; that is to say, the basic element of privatised appropriation of goods is retained, but a form of mediation (properly called here sublation - Aufhebung) is found. Thus association does not replace dissociation; rather it replicates it through developing its conditions of existence; sociation now takes the contradictory form of their unity. I agree with Reuten and Williams that dissociation is the conceptual starting point of the presentation of the bourgeois epoch; and that the exchange relation provides the first moment of association. For VFT production is private and social at the same time but expositionally we begin with dissociation to see how it is sublated by association. If that is whatis meant by 'analytically prior' we plead guilty. However the aim is to show how private concrete labour becomes socially abstract labour, not merely at themoment of exchange but prior to it. This is the way Rubin tackles the issue. He points out that in some places Marx seems to assume value and abstract labour must already be given to exchange; and in other places Marx says they presuppose exchange. In resolving this conundrum he says: ŒWe must distinguish exchange as a social form of the process of reproduction from exchange as a particular phase of this process ... alternating with the phase of direct production.¹ So what Rubin emphasises is that, if production is production for exchange, this Œleaves its imprint on the course of the process of production itself¹.# This is why value and abstract labour are forms arising from a process of production oriented to exchange; but if exchange is taken narrowly, in opposition to production, they may be posited as prior to it. This is at one level very obvious. If value and labour are commensurated in exchange, then anyone organising production for exchange is forced to Œprecommensurate¹ (to borrow a term from Reuten), assigning an Œideal value¹ to be tested against actuality in exchange and competition. Of course the producer may not be aware that socially necessary labour time has just changed, but in the long run exchange mediates supposedly autonomous production units so as to constrain them accordingly. Alfredo says without explanation this is 'invalid' (n.32 p. 122) but it seems the way in to the solution to me. The problem with Rubin is that the notion of 'imprint' is vague. There are two possible readings: to preexist 'ideally' is ambiguous; in one sense value is always ideal in the sense of not empirically observable; yet ideal forms are as real and effective as material shapes: another sense is mental. One is that there is a mental picture in the head of the capitalist about the value he hopes to realise and the methods available to him to meet his target. Secondly is that the whole circuit of capital, including the phase of production, is FORM-DETERMINED. This last notion does not appear in Alfredo but it is a significant noption in VFT. The effectivity of the VF on that which takes VF is suchthat all phases are posited as imbued with value, which is now presupposed as produced before being exchanged for the purpose of realising it. A makes an interesting point (28) when he says failure to sell on a VF theory must mean no value was created whereas on his view it was created but then destroyed as the goods rusted in the warehouse. Usually one would take the latter view as a vulgar metaphysical labour-embodied notion. But, as I say, situated in a circuit of capital that is form-determined as value in motion one could accept it. Alf (27-8) says 'the essential separation is between wage workers and the means of production'. But a) this is no more essential than the other two separations listed above b) well within the problematic of VFT. The Weeks quotation about the collective laborer is beside the point because this labour still requires social validation in exchange. There is a sense in which labour is immediately social *within* the factory; but when embodied in a C it is private *with respect to the factory's external relations*. p. 29 VFT 'conflates money with the substance of value'. This is very obscure. What is meant? Labour is the source of value; the term 'substance' is treated with suspicion by Reuten because he conflates it with material stuff and hence a embodied labour theory. But 'immaterial substance' is metaphysically kosher; for me value is such a substance which is phenomenally represented in money, and has no reality unless itis so representable. (I have a forthcoming paper on 'Money as the Form of Value'). Chris A 17 Bristol Road, Brighton, BN2 1AP, England
This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Sat Aug 24 2002 - 00:00:03 EDT