From: Gerald A. Levy (Gerald_A_Levy@MSN.COM)
Date: Wed Apr 21 2004 - 13:22:31 EDT
----- Original Message ----- From: "andromeda246" <andromeda246@hetnet.nl> Sent: Wednesday, April 21, 2004 8:55 AM Subject: Marx's concept of production-price Hi Jerry, I failed to make one point explicit in talking about "production-prices", which, to my knowledge was never really discussed much by Marxists. Just quickly summarising, Marx defined a "sectoral production price" as an "average cost-price + average profit" per unit of output, or per sectoral output, which (i) expressed the market valuation of the consumption of a quantity of labor-time and materials in producing a new output, (ii) assumed an existing, relatively stable monetarily effective demand for which producers compete (a developed market), (iii) expressed the constraint that production of output is conditional on accumulation of capital, (iv) imposed a given cost structure and a given demand structure on enterprises ("the state of the market"), (v) assumed a fairly uniform, socially imposed rate of surplus-value. In my reply to Paul Cockshott on the transformation problem on Marxmail, I mentioned different types of cost-price (ex ante and ex post) and distinguished clearly between "capital advanced" and "capital consumption". But, Marx also argued, (i) if goods are traded by intermediaries prior to reaching the final consumer, then the total surplus-value component in the capital value of those goods is not realised by the direct producers, because part of that surplus-value is realised by the intermediaries through consecutive exchanges, prior to reaching the final consumer. (ii) the market price of an output could change during the temporal interval between the point at which it has been produced, and the point at which it has been purchased by the consumer. (iii) thus, implicitly, although a given Marxian output value was produced in terms of labor-hours, this value only "regulated" the trend in the market price of that output relative to other outputs, which could deviate from that value. This already establishes that all Marx really does is define what he thinks are the basic parameters/dynamics of competition and the basic determinants of relative price movements. However, for the discerning reader, the question about production-prices then arises, "the average profit of what exactly ?", i.e. the issue is then whether the "profit" component in the production-price, as a "regulating average price" which would act as an economic norm, refers to: (A) either the total surplus-value component in the Marxian output value of a sector, or (B) only that fraction of surplus-value actually realised by the direct producers of that output, as distinct from the surplus-value realised by financial intermediaries between producers and consumers through consecutive exchanges. In other words, do the regulating "production-prices" of outputs which industries have to contend with, pertain to: (a) exclusively the regulation of an average selling price realised by producer enterprises themselves ("producers' input and output prices") - in this case, production prices apply only to what statisticians call "producer goods"; or, does it pertain instead to (b) the regulation of market prices paid by the final consumers ("final prices of both producer and consumer goods") We need to establish this, because: (a) otherwise we cannot coherently define and explain the basics of the regulation of market prices over time, and certainly for measuring the trend in prices, we need to consider the timing of transactions. This is really the "rational kernel" in Von Bortciewicz query, even although his simultaneous equations ignored the dimension of time. (b) it importantly affects our understanding of structural unequal exchange (founded on differences in the valuation of labor-time which affect cost-prices and profit rates). In Marx's own simple models of the distribution of surplus-values, which he sketched in the draft manuscript of Vol. 3 of his book, he often just suggests cavalierly "let's just take three capitals of different compositions, and then look at what happens to profits" and so on. In doing so, he really conflates a sectoral distribution of profit in respect to one type of output, with an insectoral distribution of profit in respect of different outputs, implicitly suggesting that, from the point of view of the logic of capital accumulation in general or the reproduction of total social capital, this difference really doesn't matter very much, because it's all just the same process operating, the same logic, the "quest for maximum surplus values" (we aren't even talking here yet about foreign trade). But the difference obviously does matter, because different use-values and product-chains are involved, and moreover, interpretations (A) and (B) mentioned above really imply different ways of looking at the division of labor, which Marx himself frequently conflates in his draft manuscripts, even when looking just one output: (a) from the standpoint of the capital value of the commodity itself (b) from the standpoint of competing producers who produce, or handle, a similar or identical output; (c) from the standpoint of the final consumers of an output. After all, a product is first produced, and has a capital value at that point; then it is normally transported, and may be packaged/physically preserved in wholesaling and retailing, which: (i) adds a labour-cost to it while modifying the use-value of the product, and (ii) adds value to the product (iii) may change in its price through financial intermediation (iv) may change in production value due to changes in production conditions If we looked at the real cost structure of just one new output produced, in terms of the Marxian capital value that it has at the point of purchase by the final consumer, then we would obtain a lengthy list of components which are paid out of newly generated gross income from consecutive sales of the same product, which might include: - direct producer's wage-costs - conserved value of constant capital inputs transferred by labor to new output (materials used up + real consumption of fixed equipment) in production - producers profit - insurer's profit - property and land rents - royalties, license fees and consultancy fees - creditor's profit - security company and legal firm's profit - transporters wage-cost - transporters profit and wage-cost - wholesalers profit and wage-cost (in respect of physical preserving or alteration of use-value in storage) - other commercial intermediary's profit - net government taxes, duties and levies - retailers wage-cost (in respect of physical transformation, physical display and physical preserving of use-value) - retailers profit This way of looking at things shows why the concept of "material use-value" was so important for Marx in his analysis, because without it, we could not understand at all, where the product-chain begins and ends. Another way of putting this is, that the product-chain (the formation process of a use-value) should really be viewed from the point of view of the final consumer. I think that in Marx's value theory, the "average profit" component of the production-price must be understood to refer to the total of the surplus-value component in the value of the commodity distributed among the direct producers, as well as intermediaries between producers and consumers. I think that this is the only interpretation which is consistent with Marx's discussion of the reproduction of total social capital in Capital Volume 2, and that this interpretation is really necessary to understand the systemic "law of motion" governing competition between private enterprises over the distribution of surplus-values, for which the capturing of existing real demand and strengthening relative bargaining position are the means. Thus, for example, whereas in the competitive process, (i) in the short-term the saturation of final demand and excess capacity may generate a search for intermediaries to offload output, (ii) the long-term law of motion is really the reduction of the scope of that intermediation. (This means that net output aggregates in national accounts don't really reflect the type of production prices Marx has in mind, and would have the reconstructed using I/O tables) I specifically wanted to note this point about my interpretation of production-prices, because it brings out, in another way, three aspects of Marx's theory: (1) the necessary temporal discrepancy between value and price: from the point of view of total social capital, whereas a product has a value (c+v+s) at the point of production, yet, what this value is, cannot be really manifest until the product is purchased by the final consumer, because of: (i) the temporal lag between production of output and final purchase of output, (ii) differences in productivity growth rates, (iii) relative growth rates of supply and demand, (vi) price competition, (v) monetary and credit policy Thus, as I have argued oftentimes, total volume of surplus-value produced even in theory cannot be equal to the volume of profit realised, as Marx himself admits; instead, the changes in the volumes of surplus-value produced determine the movements in profit volumes, i.e. the trend in realised profit/interest/rent income "tracks" the trend in surplus-values (as suggested by I.I. Rubin's analysis). (2) that the "vicissitudes" of competition in the intermediation between the direct producers and the consumers, including monetary policy and foreign trade, can independently affect the movements of sectoral production-prices (R. Hilferding). In a more developed market, there are normally more commercial intermediaries and a more complex commercialised division of labor (Bohm Bawerk's "roundabout way of production") and in a less developed market there are normally less commercial intermediaries and a less complex commercialised division of labor. (3) the real substance of Marx's discussion of the "tendency towards the equalisation of profit rates", namely, that from the point of view of the capitalist system as a whole, what intercapitalist competition is ultimately about, is increasing private investors' own shares in the surplus-value component of the capital value of output ("returning value to shareholders"), even although this seems to take the observable economic form of enterprises competing for shares of market demand (J. Weeks, A. Shaikh). In modern parlance, to really understand the overall logic of capitalist competition, you need to look more at "the investor's viewpoint", not simply "the functioning manager's viewpoint" - as Marx analyses in Capital Vol. 2, the investor can invest alternatively in "money capital" (financial assets - equities, bonds, stocks, securities), "production capital" (productive assets - labor and labor-services, plant & equipment, materials) or "commodity capital" (tradeable goods or fixed assets). If you look at corporate strategy, then you will see that usually corporations try to control or influence as much of the product-chain as they can, insofar as it is compatible with acceptable market risk, for the purpose of obtaining long-term surplus-profits, something which in the Marxian theory implies an "objective socialisation of labor" that is a potential foundation for planned economy. Quite simply, the fewer competing suppliers there are, for a given market demand, (i) the less "market uncertainty" there is, and (ii) the more the supplier is able to set prices. And if you look at what really happens in economic crises (recessions, downturns and depressions), then you will see that it includes the rationalisation of product-chains through take-overs and mergers, i.e. if the growth rate of the total volume of profit declines, an attempt is made to increase profit shares at the expense of other enterprises, through take-overs, mergers, asset-stripping, and so on (this in addition to an increase in the rate of surplus-value). In their book "On the economic theory of socialism", Oskar Lange and Fred Taylor considered the "parametric character of prices" in their theory of pricing and price regulation. That is to say, whereas price formation in markets results from the autonomous decisions of a multitude of different consumers and producers, in the real world they all behave as if actual prices with which they are confronted are fairly definite and fixed, a given datum (or at least can vary only within a very narrow band); the main exception being the (currently still popular) speculation in the price-fluctuations of equities, currencies, commodities, and derivatives (accumulation of capital from price-fluctuations). The main reason is that for most people, the time and ability they have to negotiate purchase prices is limited, especially because the bulk of the unit values of the products and services purchased (ordinary consumer durables and perishables) is comparatively small. Indeed, most people actually try to reduce the time they spend on buying and selling (outside of their professional occupation that is). In Morocco, the average negotiation-time per person in product sales might possibly be somewhat higher than in the Netherlands; and, in an less developed market, the total number of negotiation hours with respect to prices of household goods and services may be higher than in more developed markets; even so, the limits I mention describe the basic reality for the vast majority of actual prices. Thus, price fluctuations within respect to a given market demand must in reality be seen as the end result of a multitude of responses of producers and consumers to existing prices which manifest themselves as more or less "fixed". This more realistic interpretation of prices is the direct opposite of neoclassical ideologies about "consumer sovereignity" and suchlike, according to which every price is: (a) the outcome of a negotiation (b) a response to consumer preference and (c) consumers have an "encyclopedic knowledge of prices" as Marx puts it satirically at the beginning of his magnum opus. This doesn't adequately describe the real situation in modern capitalism because: (i) whereas some product and service prices are certainly negotiable or negotiated in some significant sense (especially more expensive durables), the majority aren't or are so only within a narrow range - if anything, more often negotiation concerns "who" should buy them or pay for them; (ii) the market knowledge which most consumers have of price levels, price relativities and price changes is limited, and the time and choices they have in buying products is limited; (iii) if prices are adjusted, they are adjusted mainly not directly in response to "consumer preferences" between alternative purchase options, but in response to a total volume of monetarily effective demand actually expressed through actual purchases, from which preferences may be inferred (though not with absolute certainty; hence surveys of the exact motive for buying decisions); (iv) what the specific preferences being exercised are, is something typically known only indirectly and aposteriori through actual prices paid for products and services; (v) consumer preferences are investigated through surveys, typically to assist prediction or development of a future demand for products and services, complementing projections from the past trends in the actual volume of purchases. The objection made here is that if somebody opts to buy good X rather than Y, he has "implicitly" negotiated through exercising consumer preference between alternative choices, but the point is that neither the price of X or the price of Y have themselves been negotiated. It is this basic economic reality I have described, which justifies the concept of a "regulating price" or "natural price" as applied by the classical political economists and Marx, which imposes itself on economic actors, and which explains why the subjective theories of value don't adequately describe prices and pricing, never mind explaining them. Contrary to what vulgar economists say, in socialist-type economic theory (e.g. Lange, Kornai, Itoh) a much more sophisticated and more realistic understanding of the functioning of prices emerges than in the standard neoclassicist textbook vision. Vulgar economists might argue that socialist-type economies in the past worked badly from the point of view of satisfying consumer needs, but they typically forget that mostly those economies: (i) emerged out of wars. (i) were launched from a starting-point of comparatively low labor productivity. (ii) had political institutions which were often rather despotic and rigid. (iii) were under constant threat from imperialist aggression. (v) lacked the experience of developed national markets. Obviously, very good economic theory can co-exist with very badly operated economies; that just depends on who happens to be in charge and what policies are pursued. It would be idealist to think that the best scientific theory would necessarily always be adopted by politicians, i.e. that objective truth is always compatible with partisan interests, rather than that what the objective truth is disputed by partisan interests. Arguably, the "telecommunications and information technology revolution" means that prices could in principle be adjusted much faster to consumer preferences than before. This is technically true, but the real question is whether they really do, especially under monopolistic conditions and given power relations. As Prof. Perelman has emphasised, price levels and price relativities in the real world often have rather a lot to do with "the capacity to impose prices on buyers" by one means or another. Speculative bubbles create the possibility for revaluing a perceived "human capital" of a group of individuals (or even a nation) and thus alter terms of exchange, but in the last instance: (i) the "capitalisation of human capital" depends on an already existing buying power for that human capital (an already existing real demand); (ii) the speculative bubble is sustained by the extension of credit, allowing human capital to be overvalued; (iii) if the increased value attached to the human capital of individuals (their revaluation as being "worth more") is not matched by any real increase in output of tangible products and services, it is really to a large extent a "fictitious capital", which disappears when aggregate demand growth tapers off or falls, or if competitors produce the same output or a higher output with producers whose "human capital" was supposed to be lower. (iv) in an overall sense, price relativities and price levels reflect the relative bargaining positions and power relationships between social classes and nations. (v) Even if modern information technology makes a better adjustment of supply to demand possible, price relativities and price levels still operate under the constraint of production-cost and a pattern of distribution of buying power, if price competition occurs in an open market. That's all for now. Regards, Jurriaan
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Thu Apr 22 2004 - 00:00:01 EDT