Introduction: Marx’s Capital in the Struggle for a New Human
Society
by Andrew
Kliman
This special issue of The Hobgoblin on Marx’s Capital carries three chapters of Raya
Dunayevskaya’s 1958 Marxism and Freedom
which analyze and comment on all three volumes of Capital, as well as her late 1970s’
critiques of Ernest Mandel’s “Introduction” to Volume I and of Roman Rosdolsky
on Marx’s method. Also included are
new essays by Dave Black on the concept of value and Chris Ford on the free
association of producers.
In the face of unprecedented
retrogression, the struggle for new human relations continues. A whole new movement against
exploitative global capital has emerged, and tens of millions of people
worldwide have mobilized in opposition to the
These self-imposed limits should not be confused with realism and practicality. TINA has led to the resurgence of an unrealistic, almost desperate hope that, though capitalism is here to stay, it can nonetheless be reformed in a fundamental and sustainable way. How else can we account for the renewed popularity of social democracy, even though it collapsed everywhere just as Russian state-capitalism did, unable to sustain itself and its reforms in the face of neoliberal reaction? Moreover, the theoretical basis of calls for “fair exchange,” more representative international financial and political institutions, “living wages,” and similar nostrums is, all too often, unrealistic hope that fundamental reform is sustainable.
What we need, I think, is a
different sort of hope, hope grounded in real possibilities for a better future,
and a different sort of thinking – dialectical thinking – that can help us
search out and develop the real possibilities that TINA-think assumes away. Capital continues to deserve careful
study as a prime example of revolutionary dialectical methodology in
action. Although many leftist
theorists today regard the dialectic as an expression of capital’s “totalizing”
logic, in Marx’s hands the dialectic “includes in its positive understanding of
what exists a simultaneous recognition of its negation, its inevitable
destruction; … it regards every historically developed form as being in a fluid
state, in motion, and therefore grasps its transient aspect as well; … it does
not let itself be impressed by anything, being in its very essence critical and
revolutionary” (Marx, Postface to
the 2nd ed. of Capital,
Vol. I).
Thus, although Mandel’s
“Introduction” and other commentaries try to divide Marx into a revolutionary
and a “strictly scientific” economist, this division is untenable. From the dual character of the commodity
on the first page, to Volume III’s law of the tendential fall in the rate of
profit, the internal contradictions of which produce economic crises, Capital’s “positive” theory of how
capitalism functions includes
“negativity” within itself. The system’s dualities and internal
contradictions are what make it inherently unstable and therefore something
humankind can transcend. At each
moment, however, discerning how this abstract possibility can become a real one
requires a lot of hard thinking.
Another reason why Capital continues to have direct implications for political practice is that Marx was taking on ideologies quite similar to those of our day. On the one hand, he combats the TINA-think of bourgeois political economy (“there has been history, but there is no longer any”). At the same time, he combats the political economy of Proudhon and other leftists who claimed that the ills of capitalism can be ameliorated by reforming monetary, exchange, and financial relations, while leaving the capitalist mode of production intact.
This latter dimension of Capital is often suppressed. Some leftists do not want the
specificity of Marx’s ideas to interfere with their calls for us to “unite” –
behind them; others want to attach his name to perspectives and projects that
have more in common with the tendencies he fought than with his own ideas. Marx himself, however, continually
fought for his specific ideas within the movement, especially once Capital was published and available for
all to study. In 1875, the
“Marxist” (
When Capital is considered as a critique of bourgeois political economy only, not a critique of Proudhonist political economy as well, some of it becomes inscrutable or even pointless. Consider section 3 of the first chapter, on “the value-form.” This section contains an intricate dialectical derivation of money from the commodity form, but what is the point? Marx is emphatic that this derivation is crucial – “we have to perform a task … we have to show … we have to trace” – but why? The answer, I believe, is that he is showing money to be a necessary consequence of commodity production. In order to do away with the social ills associated with money and exchange, it is necessary to do away with commodity production. Conversely, as long as commodity production remains, so must money and the social ills associated with it. As Marx had written earlier, in a critique of Darimon, a Proudhonist, “it is impossible to abolish money itself as long as exchange value remains the social form of products. It is necessary to see this clearly in order to avoid setting impossible tasks, and in order to know the limits [of] monetary reforms and transformations of circulation [commodity exchange]” (Marx, Grundrisse, Vintage Books, p. 145).
Some of what she said about Capital is more widely recognized today
than when she wrote, and a whole
Thus, much of what Marx
said, and Dunayevskaya reclaimed, about the relationship between production and
the market has yet to be understood, much less internalized. Consider another statement from Volume
II to which she draws attention:
“The peculiar characteristic is not that the commodity, labor power, is
saleable, but that labor power appears in the shape of a commodity.” “Huh?,” one can hear frustrated and
bemused readers ask. “What is a
commodity if not something saleable?”
If Marx was right that the commodification of workers’ labour power
(capacity to work) is the defining characteristic of the capitalist epoch, then
those who want to transcend this epoch would do well not to let the question
remain a rhetorical one.
What made Dunayevskaya singularly able to
reclaim dimensions of Capital that
many overlooked or found opaque – and others have suppressed – was her
conviction that Stalinist Russia was a state-capitalist society, together with
her felt need to substantiate that conviction by grounding it in Marx’s
theory.
Thus Dunayevskaya’s
presentation of her new interpretation of Capital is tightly interwoven with her
analysis of
*
*
*
Reading Dunayevskaya on
Marx, however, is no substitute for reading Marx – nor do I think she meant it
to be. Her commentaries on Capital are all “argumentative” rather
than “expository”; they are interventions on specific issues that sometimes
presuppose the reader’s familiarity with the book, not attempts to popularize it
or tell us “everything we need to know” about it. She regarded Mandel’s lengthy
introduction to Volume I of Capital
as a “burden” on the work and a “vulgarization” that presented his views
instead of Marx’s. The particular
content of his introduction is no doubt part of what angered her, yet,
especially in the last decade of her life, Dunayevskaya also expressed profound
dissatisfaction with how even the best “post-Marx Marxists,” such as Engels, had
treated Marx’s work. Because they
were overly confident that they understood his work, she argued, they too gave
us popularizations that presented their views as his. (See “Marxist-Humanism’s Challenge to
All Post-Marx Marxists,” in the 2nd ed. of Dunayevskaya’s Rosa Luxemburg, Women’s Liberation, and
Marx’s Philosophy of Revolution, Univ. of Illinois Press,
1991.)
In the case of a book like
Capital, there is a constant
temptation to rely on popularizations, as well as a temptation to read
commentaries like Dunayevskaya’s as if they provided the same “assistance.” I think it is crucial to resist such
temptations. Precisely because Capital is so difficult and complexly
structured, one ends up either reading the popularization instead of the book,
or reading the book through the popularizer’s eyes, lightly glancing over
unfamiliar things and finding (of course!) that the rest confirms what one
already “knows.” Unfortunately,
what has long been said about there being “no royal road to science” is true.
I’d like to conclude with a
comment on another kind of resistance to the patient, methodical study that a
work like Capital demands of the
reader. Like much of the 1960s’ New
Left, many young leftists today think that “too much” emphasis on theory is a
bad thing, that it leads to hierarchy and the authoritarian vanguard party. I consider this a radical
misdiagnosis. The vanguard parties
were long on flexibility and short on genuine theoretical reflection and
development. (I recently learned
that the U.S. Communist Party held classes at its