http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=2381
Tom Huhn (ed.)
The Cambridge Companion to Adorno
Tom Huhn (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Adorno, Cambridge
University Press, 2004, 428pp, $26.99 (pbk), ISBN 0521775000.
Reviewed by Eduardo Mendieta, State University of New York, Stony
Brook
Great thinking is always majestic and towering in its failure, as
it speaks in signs and aphorism to an age echoing in the distance .
Theodor W. Adorno (1903-1969) is one of those great thinkers beginning
to be rescued and listened to as if for the first time, without the
cacophony of his own time drowning the sounds of his philosophical
music. 2003 marked the centenary of his birth and with it also came
the conferences and congresses, and publication of a series of
biographies[1], and bibliographical references, like the companion
here under review. Dealing with Adorno's oeuvre is a truly daunting
task, not merely because of its staggering size; presently we have the
collected works in 20 volumes, made up actually of some 23 books,
averaging 600 pages a book. In 1993 Suhrkamp Verlag began the
publication of Adorno's Nachgelassene Schriften [Posthumous Works] in
30 volumes, made up of six sections, containing 17 volumes of lectures
(some of which have been already translated) and 5 volumes of
philosophical notebooks, in addition to numerous volumes of
correspondence with Walter Benjamin, Max Horkheimer, Alban Berg, and
his parents.
The amount of his output is matched only by the prodigiousness of the
style. Adorno's works abounds in aphorisms, making almost every line
quotable -- my undergraduate copy of the English translation of
Negative Dialectics has almost every other line underlined. Only two
other thinkers of the German language are comparable, Martin Heidegger
and Ernst Bloch, although only in Adorno is the dialectic between
language and thought suspended in such a way that the one does not
become a handmaid of the other. In contrast to Heidegger's Teutonic
boomings, Greco-Germanic archaism, and hackneyed etymologies, Adorno's
style indulges neither imperial nostalgias nor consolations in the
tune of angelic voices calling from the forests of time. In contrast
to Bloch's eulogies to the German language and the cadences of spoken
dialects, with their colloquialism and their endearment with pithy
child-like philosophical ditties, Adorno's style rubs everyday
language against the roughness of dialectical rigor, and the sounds of
foreign words interspersed throughout make sure that language never
forgets that its speaks in many tones and possibly thinks at the
rhythm of other tunes. Adorno's style sobers, prickles, annoys; it is
a cold splash of reason that refuses to be seduced by its own clarity.
Adorno's thinking, however, knows that it must think in language, and
this is at once its blessing and damnation It is also the type of
thinking that is indebted to language, yet in its dependence, it
realizes that the concept, enunciated in language, betrays that which
its reaches out to grasp, returning thinking to the insufficiency of
its endeavors. Adorno himself thought that "[p]hilosophy is
essentially its language, philosophical problems are by and large
problems of language, and the alleged independence of language from
things that is found in the so-called positive sciences, does not
apply in the same way for philosophy"[2]
In the English-speaking world, the complicity and promiscuous embrace
between language and thought in Adorno's thinking has created
understandable reticence to engage his work. The extant translations,
dating from the sixties and seventies, have been denounced as wanting
and even misleading. In 2002 Stanford University Press issued a new
translation of The Dialectic of Enlightenment, and Robert
Hullot-Kentor hadd already published in 1998 a new translation of
Aesthetic Theory, to replace the one published in 1984 by Christian
Lenhardt. He is also preparing a new translation of Negative
Dialectics to replace the 1983 translation by E. B. Ashton. It is
almost as if we are beginning to treat Adorno as if he were two
millennia removed from us, and German had become a dead tongue. An
equally important reason for Adorno's challenge is the breath of his
overall contribution to the humanities and social sciences. His
complete works contain studies on the authoritarian personality, the
culture industry and mass culture, sociological treatises on music,
numerous essays on sociological themes and concepts, reflections on
Marxism, all of it woven with learned reconstructions of social
theory, the history of philosophy with its terminologies, and
brilliantly original readings of canonical figures. Adorno's work
spans one of the most ghastly periods in recent history, and his
thinking registered the horrors,
Still, one may safely aver that Adorno's work can be accessed in terms
of its relationship and contribution to what has been called left
Hegelianism, on the one hand, and historical materialism, on the
other. Adorno is surely the most Hegelian of 20th century
philosophers, in more ways than those who toiled with phenomenology,
existentialism, pragmatism, and Nietzschean genealogy, were trying to
come to terms with the fragments of an irreversibly shattered
totality, but got caught in its shards and tangles. Reason can only be
approached by way of conceptual ruin, and the ruins of the concept. If
Hegelianism is about both totality and mediation, identity and
difference, then Adorno was the most Hegelian of 20th century
thinkers, who also, however, refused to embrace the Hegelian tale of
ultimate reconciliation, or buy into the presupposed theodicy of the
Golgotha of reason becoming freedom in history through endless
suffering. If Geist, reason, is its history, this history remains a
scar and no cauterization will conceal it under the smooth neoplasm of
world-historical platitudes. Today, as Adorno said in so many ways,
everything that is social and natural is thoroughly mediated, but the
vehicle of the mediation is itself distorted by the "totality."
There is no outside, only the mediated meditation, the trace of the
whole in everything singular, and the singular as a monad that mirrors
the whole. This mediated mediation, however, is always the commodity
form. The concept itself has succumbed to the theological incantations
of the circulation of wares and exchange values. The concept itself,
as Lukýcs had already shown in his History and Class Consciousness,
and as Adorno never ceased to underscore, wore the scarlet letter of
the market of commodities. For this reason, one may safely claim, that
along with Fredric Jameson, Adorno was one of the great Marxist
dialecticians of the 20th century.
With these claims, we have already anticipated how to begin to
evaluate The Cambridge Companion to Adorno. Although the editor did an
outstanding job of introducing the essays, and gathering a stellar
group of scholars, the book fails as a unity . There are some truly
outstanding contributions in this volume. J. M. Bernstein's and Simon
Jarvis's soon to be canonical essays are gems of philosophical
reflection that are first-rate contributions to Hegelian, Marxist, and
Adornian scholarship. After Bernstein's essay it will be easier to
understand how Adorno was an anti-Hegelian Hegelian, and how faithful
Hegelians can only be so as anti-Hegelians. Jarvis's essay rightly
draws the contours of Adorno's historical materialism, and elucidates
the ways in which Adorno's philosophical system was a close commentary
and explication of Marx's Grundrisse and Kapital. The essays by
Christoph Menke and Gerhard Schweppenh·user explicate the ways in
which Adorno contributed to the debate among Kant, Hegel, and
Nietzsche on the relationship between freedom, morality, ethics, and
justice, and how Adorno, therefore, should become a dialogue partner
for second- and third-generation Critical Theorists as they study the
nature of communicative freedom, dialogic solidarity, and substantive
justice. The book is arguably weighted down by too many contributions
on Adorno's work on the philosophy and sociology of the production and
consumption of music. These essays, however, are also deformed by an
eagerness to depict an Adorno in contradiction and aporia, an attitude
more appropriate for scholarly journals and less so for tools of
reference. James Schmidt's essay on Adorno's contributions to Thomas
Mann's Doktor Faustus and his tortured relationship with Arnold
Schoenberg is an important contribution to the intellectual history of
a decisive period in Euro-American migrations and diasporas. It should
be read as a preemptive answer to Robert Hullot-Kentor's mystifying
contribution, which unfolds an utopian aspect of Adorno's work on the
grounds of a disconcerting assumption, namely that Adorno's work
should be doubly alienated from the United States, the country that
always stands in his work as a metonym for totality and modernity, and
has served as the very material condition of possibility of most of
his work. In more than one way, Adorno's work was a meditation on
America, and that there may be interest on his obtuse and hermetic
work in the US should not be "puzzling," but both expectable
and inevitable. In fact, Adorno may be needed more in the US than in
Germany or Europe in general.
In addition to some of these shortcomings, the book fails to cover
some significant territory in Adorno scholarship. Adorno's
relationship to Benjamin is not substantively addressed, and this is a
major oversight, especially as Adorno's work is so much a commentary
on what is promised and left unresolved in Benjamin's mangled torso of
a work. Another twin to Benjamin, Ernst Bloch, is only mentioned once,
but not discussed at all. No justice is done to Adorno's Negative
Dialectics if it is not read in tandem with Bloch's Principle of Hope
and Subject-Object: Clarifications on Hegel. Bloch was also a
philosopher of music, and philosopher of art, in general, who was
always in Adorno's background, much like the tain of a mirror.
Adorno's relationship to psychoanalysis and Freud should have received
more attention, notwithstanding Joel Whitebook's essay, which should
not have been included in this volume because it is less interested in
engaging Adorno's work on its on terms than in pushing Whitebook's own
intellectual project. It is simply not the case that Adorno was not
aware of the ways in which sublimation does happen in and through the
psycho-social mechanism of civilization. At the same time, however,
and Adorno did not tire of making this point, sublimation must be both
resisted and held in abeyance. This was the point of a negative
dialectics that resists all attempts at reconciliation with a reified
psychic life. Adorno's rupture with Erich Fromm, for instance, could
have been a point of departure for an insight into what type of Freud
Adorno and Horkheimer wanted to preserve. For both, the Freud of
instincts and intractable corporeality, whose suffering and desiring
remains un-sublateable and irreducible, became the alibi for a
critique of consumer culture and the discontents of civilization. It
is with reference to this Freud of tormented and tormentable bodies
that Adorno developed his "negative morality," which refuses
to reconcile Kant, or morality, and Hegel, or ethical life, because
the moral imperative wells up as a somatic "impulse" and
"stirring impatience" of the flesh. In general, a discussion
of Adorno's type of Freudianism and how it stands athwart
post-Lacanian psychoanalysis would have been most welcome.
Although there are two essays that deal with Adorno and Heidegger,
their focus militates against a more thorough and synoptic overview of
this antinomial duet. There was no contemporary thinker against whom
Adorno thought most continuously, consistently, obsessively, and
lastingly. Heidegger haunts almost every sentence in the Negative
Dialectics, precisely because Adorno thought that Heidegger was
usurping what he thought he himself was doing: overcoming metaphysics
by its immanent destruction. The question of technology was not the
only the issue that brought them into vicinity. Both thinkers dealt
extensively with questions concerning the nature of the work of art,
the role of language in thinking and philosophy, and both produced
original readings of Hegel, Kant, and Nietzsche, among others.
Finally, an essay on Adorno's role as a public intellectual in
Post-World War II Germany would have been very useful and would have
allowed readers of the volume to access the impact, both beneficial
and detrimental, to the development of West German political culture.
The prejudice that Adorno was an elitist, disengaged from public
culture, has begun to be refuted and dissolved by studies of the
archives of the Institute for Social Research, and the publication of
his extensive correspondence with colleagues, university officials,
newspaper editors, and radio station directors[3]. These drawbacks
notwithstanding, The Cambridge Companion to Adorno makes for a good
point of entry into one of the most brilliant and capacious thinkers
of the 20th century .
[1] See in particular Stefan Mller-Doohm, Adorno: Eine
Biographie (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2003), and Lorenz
J·ger, Adorno: A Political Biography (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 2004).
[2] Theodor W. Adorno, Philosophische Terminologie, Vol 1 (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1973), 7.
[3] See Alex Demirovic, Der nonkoformistische Intellektuelle. Die
Entwicklung der Kritischen Theorie zur Frankfurter Schule (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1999). See the thorough review essay by Max
Pensky, "Beyond the Message in the Bottle: The Other Critical
Theory" Constellations, Vol. 10, No. 1 (2003) 135-144. See also
Jrgen Habermas's essay on Adorno's centennial celebration,
"Dual-Layered Time: Personal Notes on Philosopher T. W. Adorno in
the '50's" Logos 2.4 (Fall 2003), available on-line at:
http://www.logosjournal.com/