http://www.philosophersnet.com/cafe/cafearticle.php?name=philosopher
Philosopher of the Month: Theodor Adorno
Jack Furlong
A critic of modern jazz, a key theoretician of the left and a leader
in the most celebrated academic institute of the last century, Theodor
Weisengrund Adorno combined the intense speculative focus of a German
academic with the feel for the concrete of a French aesthete. Along
the way, he also unwittingly became a model - and a foil - for
Anglo-American culture critics.
As a teenager, Adorno spent many Saturday afternoons poring over
Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason with Siegfried Kracauer, who
encouraged him to read philosophy in its socio-historical context and
to apply philosophical and sociological tools to understand such
cultural artefacts as film. Not surprisingly, as an undergraduate, he
applied himself to philosophy, psychology and sociology and, after
spending three years studying music in Vienna with avant-garde
composers, he completed his doctoral degree requirements and began
writing. His work over the span of forty years never lost the
connectivity of art, philosophy and cultural criticism that so
enthralled him in his early reading of Kant with Kracauer.
Adorno wrote most of his mature work under the aegis of the celebrated
Institute for Social Research. He officially joined in 1938, but his
relationship with its guiding spirit and founder, Max Horkheimer,
began in the 1920s when they took courses together. Along with several
others, they began a collaborative research programme within the
Institute called the Frankfurt School of Critical Theory. Under
Horkheimer and Adorno, the school dedicated itself to producing
research characterized by the systematic rejection of closed
philosophical and political systems, and a commitment to ongoing study
and criticism of current oppressive sociopolitical structures. Less
interested in Marx's reductionist critique of capitalism than
traditional Marxists, the Frankfurt School sought to expand his
criticisms of bourgeois culture. Less preoccupied with praxis
(revolutionary action) than with theoretical insight into oppressive
structures and processes, the school was often charged by more
orthodox Marxists with elitism and passivity. This accent on culture
and the charge of elitism have marked Adorno's career.
Adorno would put himself in the same group as Hegel, Marx and others
who used the form of argumentation known as dialectics to unmask the
hypocrisies and absurdities of the political and social status quo.
Contemporary bourgeois life requires that all of its aspects be
controlled - the statehouse, the family, the church, the airwaves,
the marketplace. This 'administered world' needs homogenized
certainties, concepts taken for granted unfailingly, in order to
maintain total control. Hence, says Adorno, modern regimes 'reify'
- make into a thing - and quantify what cannot be fashioned into
permanent concepts and identifies, but which nonetheless prove useful
to those who rule. For Adorno, the most tragic manifestation of this
'administered world' was the Holocaust, in which even human beings
themselves were 'reified' - counted, recorded and, eventually,
'consumed'.
Dominating regimes must run according to political theories made of
clear, determined concepts and predictable logic - a closed system.
Philosophy for Adorno contests this desire for conceptual and
systematic finality, for philosophical concepts resist their own
closure. So understood, philosophy is dialectics, or 'thought driven
by its own insufficiency.' Philosophy must constantly criticize
itself, preventing the negative energy of thinking from getting
short-circuited by conformity.
Art, too, like philosophy, can liberate people from the claustrophobia
of power. 'Works of art,' states Adorno 'are social products
which have discarded the illusion of being-for-society, an illusion
tendentiously maintained by all other commodities.' To the extent
that art gives people what they expected, it becomes a
commodity.
This theme appears vividly in Adorno's best known book, Dialectic of
Enlightenment (1947), co-authored by Horkheimer. The authors first
describe how the Enlightenment concept of reason became an efficient
tool for social and political administrations to ensure the compliance
of the administered at all levels of discourse and practice.
'Through the countless agencies of mass production and its culture the
conventionalised modes of behaviour are impressed on the individual as
the only natural, respectable, and rational ones. He defines himself
only as a thing.' Even art becomes commodified, an example of
'instrumental reason', producing what the authors call 'the
culture industry'.
Though written in the 1940s this critique has not lost its relevance:
speaking about what they saw as a growing monopoly, Adorno and
Horkheimer claimed that 'Movies and radio need no longer pretend to
be art. The truth that they are just business is made into an ideology
in order to justify the rubbish they deliberately produce.' Widely
anthologized, this chapter on the culture industry has inspired and
guided the relatively new field of culture studies in the social
sciences and humanities.
In the last year of his life, Adorno became embattled with radical
students, and charges of elitism unfortunately made his last few
months stressful. Yet Adorno's reputation survived to the extent
that, currently, his is often claimed as a precursor to postmodern and
post-structuralist thought.
Suggested reading
Adorno, T. 1991. The Culture Industry: Selected essays on mass
culture. London: Routledge.
O'Connor, B. 2000 (ed.). The Adorno Reader. Oxford: Blackwell.
Horkheimer, M & Adorno, T. W. 1976 [1947], Dialectic of
Enlightenment. London: Continuum.