From: glevy@PRATT.EDU
Date: Tue Feb 14 2006 - 10:01:59 EST
Those who are concerned about complexity theory and dynamic analysis and its relation to Classical and Marxian theory will be interested in a recent (2006) review by Barkley Rosser of the short (2003) book by Duncan Foley. In solidarity, Jerry ------------------------------------------------------------------ Unholy Trinity: Labor, capital, and land in the new economy. Duncan K. Foley. 2003. London: Routledge, 98 pages, index. Duncan Foley's Unholy Trinity: Labor, capital, and land in the new economy is the sixth in the series of Graz Schumpeter Lectures published by Routledge, all relatively slim volumes elucidating themes arguably related to Schumpeter, if just peripherally, and that usually summarize major arguments of the authors (previous authors were Stanley Metcalfe, Brian Loasby, Nathan Rosenberg, Ian Steedman, and Erich Streissler). In this one, which deals with questions of induced technological change in several sections, Foley attempts to provide an integration of ideas that have evolved through his varied career, from high general equilibrium theorist (Foley, 1967), through deep student of Marxian economics (Foley, 1986), to complexity theorist (Foley, 1994; for more detailed discussion of his personal and intellectual path see Colander et al, 2004, Chapter 7). A central argument is that the classical political economists, not just Marx but also Adam Smith and Malthus with Ricardo (largely lumped together in his analysis), developed ideas that are well suited to representation and understanding using the methods of modern complexity economics, themes of dynamic out-of-equilibrium self-organization in systems with boundedly rational agents, in contrast to the requirements for full Walrasian general equilibrium that he studied early in his career. The book consists of five chapters. The first and longest, Complexity, self-organization, and political economy, presents the core arguments of the book. He argues for a direct link from classical political economy to modern complexity theory as operating through biology and evolutionary theory, from Malthus to Darwin to Kauffman (1995).The second, Innovative capitalism and the distribution of income, develops a model combining the distributional dynamics in a growth cycle model or Richard Goodwin (1967) with the innovations possibilities schedule analysis of Charles Kennedy (1964). In the third, Can political economy save us from global warming? he suggests that introducing properly priced land into his Goodwin-Kennedy model shows that the answer to the chapter's title question might be yes. The fourth, The new economy and the population of the earth, shows that there may be two stable equilibrium levels of global population, a low income-high population Malthusian one and a high income-low population Smithian one. These reflect the conflict between the increasing returns through the division of labor arguments of Smith, seen as supported by Marx, with the diminishing returns due to fixed land arguments of Malthus, seen as supported by Ricardo. The fifth chapter briefly recapitulates and comments. A major success of the book is Foley's central argument that the classical vision, especially that of Smith and Marx, can be seen as a predecessor to modern heterogeneous agent complexity models. The economy self-organizes out of the interactions between agents who are heterogeneous and boundedly rational, even as no part of the economy may be in equilibrium (although some parts may be). He adduces the classical idea of long-run normal prices around which markets fluctuate as centers of gravitation, as the key to systems with order and organization that may nevertheless always be out of equilibrium, even if in some sense these centers of gravitation are long-run equilibria (which may nevertheless themselves evolve with technological change). This emergence of a macro-level order out of an essentially micro-level disorder stands in sharp contrast with the new classical vision of macro-order arising from general micro-level equilibrium associated with representative agents with rational expectations. Another success is his reemphasis of the classical political economics concern with the distinctiveness of each of the traditional factors of production, labor, capital, and land, in contrast with the implication of neoclassical production functions that they are all essentially identical as scarce, rent-generating sources of production. He cites the arguments of the English Cantabridgians in the Cambridge capital theory controversies of the 1960s and 1970s (Harcourt, 1972) in railing against the neoclassical production function as a useful concept in understanding the real evolution of technology and production. Even so, just as he accepts the critique of aggregate production functions, he argues that in complex self-organizing economies, the aggregate of capital is an important abstraction as the classical political economists thought, with this importance showing up through the induced technological change approach. It must also be agreed that the applications of these ideas to essentially environmental themes in the third and fourth chapters are largely successful. However, I found these less stimulating and ultimately somewhat more conventional than the arguments put forth in the first two chapters. That properly pricing environmental assets may increase the likelihood of the economy being on a more sustainable long-run path is quite in line with arguments from the most conventional neoclassical models. However, it must be admitted that the agreement in principle with more conventional approaches is not necessarily a bad thing in this case. So are there some caveats to have regarding this generally elegant and well argued set of essays, aside from the caveat lector Foley himself provides at the end of his first chapter that he uses standard differential equations models for much of the book rather than the simulation models more favored by many complexity economists? Of course. One of these is a failure to fully cite certain earlier observers who saw the link between complexity and self-organization and linked this especially to the Smithian vision of classical political economy. He does cite some students of increasing returns, notably Alfred Marshall and Allyn A. Young (1927), but neither of these really had a full idea of the complex dynamics of interacting heterogeneous agents. One who did, and came to understand modern complexity theory from its origins in physics, was Friedrich Hayek (1967). He made this argument regarding self-organization in market economies. Indeed, even the principal promulgators of the general equilibrium theory itself have all in various ways understood its limits and suggested directions implying a complexity perspective, from Walras' speculations about dynamic adjustment mechanisms (Walker, 1996) to Arrow (Colander et al, 2004, Chapter 10) and even Debreu (1974). Another matter is his treatment of chaotic dynamics, which in his first chapter he contrasts rather sharply with complex dynamics, dismissing the former as an equilibrium concept in contrast with the more open and dialectically evolutionary self-organization of complex systems. This seems overdone to this observer who sees the two as more closely linked. He recognizes some similarities: both kinds of systems involve endogeneous erratic fluctuations. While chaotic ones involve a definite equilibrium and a locally unstable but globally stable fluctuation that can be characterized for forecasting statistically, he sees the complex ones as not forecastable at all and as completely open. However, his vision of the classical self-organization involves fluctuations around centers of gravitation that gradually evolve. He even notes that this is the pattern to be expected from the Malthusian demoeconomic system, which he sees as the direct predecessor of modern complex dynamics. But it is well known that the Malthusian system can easily generate fully chaotic dynamics (Day, 1983). While a single equation chaotic system will not generally evolve, there is nothing preventing the equilibria of a set of chaotic equations from doing so. As regards the question of dialectics, chaotic dynamics most generally arise from a conflict between something pressing hard against something else, as in snapback repellor dynamics or a population erratically overshooting an ecological carrying capacity, a sharp conflict. The line between chaos and complexity looks both fuzzier and narrower than Foley has drawn it here. This discussion of chaos and complexity slides into a closely related discussion, that of the relation between equilibrium and complex self-organization. Now it is perhaps too easy to see Foley as striving to move beyond the general equilibrium notions of his earliest papers to his more generalized recent view. There is an endogenously evolving order, but no equilibrium really. Or more precisely, for thermodynamical systems, self-reproducing organization occurs far from the long run equilibrium that might exist (or itself evolve). However, he does briefly recognize that complex systems might well contain subsystems that do exhibit equilibria, such as the stable temperature of blood in a more broadly non-equilibrium organism. Certainly within economies there are markets or other sub-parts where the standard story of rapid movement to partial equilibrium holds. It is well known that double auction markets rapidly and easily move to equilibria. In many more competitive markets, such as for commodities or financial assets, the dynamics we see are probably better characterized as the evolution of temporary equilibrium states that the markets are almost always in, rather than as some out-of-equilibrium processes. Probably almost no economy is ever in a full Walrasian general equilibrium, except perhaps briefly by accident, but many sub-parts probably are almost always in equilibrium, and many economies appear to be in macroeconomic equilibria, or near them, much of the time, in the sense of aggregate supply equaling aggregate demand, even if there is not necessarily full employment. Foley recognizes that there are multiple concepts of equilibrium, but only compares the steady point of a differential equations system one with the thermodynamic equilibrium one. But in dynamical systems there are quite a few others, as has been known since at least the time of Alfred J. Lotka (1925, Chapter 9). Foley's analysis of the problem of complex self-organization and equilibrium is subtle and sophisticated, but I fear that he does not fully plumb the depths of the complexities involved in the relationship between such systems and the equilibria of their sub-systems or the higher forms of equilibria that may be involved in their evolutionary dynamics. However, this is a relatively compact set of lectures. The book also does not deal at all with money, arguably the question that has been the most consistent thread thoughout most of Foley's work, a beautiful journey whose goal he admits has not arrived at yet (Colander at al, 2004, pp. 195-196). Thus, we cannot expect a fully satisfying resolution of all of these matters, and it can be pointed out they have not been solved by any others either. These caveats ultimately amount to relatively minor quibbles, fusses that a very well done book is not perfect. This neat volume is a provocative piece of thoughtful writing that delves deeply into some of the most difficult problems in economic theory. That it does not fully resolve all of them does not make it unworthy of being read or seriously considered. It is a fully worthy piece indeed. References Colander, D.; Holt, R.P.F., and Rosser, J.B., Jr. 2004. The Changing Face of Economics: Conversations with Cutting Edge Economists. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Day, R.H. 1983. The emergence of chaos from classical economic growth. Quarterly Journal of Economics 98, 201-213. Debreu, G. 1974. Excess demand functions. Journal of Mathematical Economics 1, 15-23. Foley, D.K. 1967. Resource allocation and the public sector. Yale Economic Essays 7, 43-98. Foley, D.K. 1986. Understanding Capital: Marx's Economic Theory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Foley, D.K. 1994. A statistical equilibrium theory of markets. Journal of Economic Theory 62, 321-345. Goodwin, R.M. 1967. A growth cycle. In: C.H. Feinstein (Ed.), Socialism, Capitalism and Economic Growth: Essays Presented to Maurice Dobb. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 54-58. Harcourt, G.C. 1972. Some Cambridge Controversies in the Theory of Capital. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Hayek, F.A. 1967. The theory of complex phenomena. In: Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp. 22-42. Kauffman, S.A. 1995. At Home in the Universe. London: Penguin. Kennedy, C. 1964. Induced bias in the theory of innovation and the theory of distribution. The Economic Journal 74, 541-547. Lotka, A.J. 1925. Elements of Physical Biology. Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins (reprinted in 1945 as Elements of Mathematical Biology). Walker, D.A. 1996. Walras' Market Models. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Young, A.A. 1927. Economic Problems. New and Old. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. J. Barkley Rosser, Jr. James Madison University rosserjb@jmu.edu
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Wed Feb 15 2006 - 00:00:02 EST