From: Jerry Levy (Gerald_A_Levy@MSN.COM)
Date: Mon Dec 25 2006 - 09:39:20 EST
Dogan: Yes, of course, we can discuss the subject more after the beginning of the New Year. But, before then, I'll give you some propositions and questions to ponder. Below I'm going to deconstruct part of Plekhanov's position on "humans as tool-making animals". >>> But it must not be forgotten that quantitative differences pass into qualitative. What exists as an embryo in one species of animal can become the distinguishing feature of another species of animal. This particularly applies to the use of tools. An elephant breaks off branches and uses them to brush away flies. This is interesting and instructive. But in the history of the evolution of the species “elephant” the use of branches in the fight against flies probably played no essential part; elephants did not become " by and elephants because their more or less elephant-like ancestors brushed off flies with branches. It is quite otherwise with man. The whole existence of the Australian savage depends on his boomerang, just as the whole existence of modern Britain depends on her machines. Take away from the Australian his boomerang, make him a tiller of the soil, and he of necessity will change all his mode of life, all his habits, all his manner of thinking, all his “nature.” We have said: make him a tiller of the soil. From the example of agriculture it can clearly be seen that the process of the productive action of man on nature presupposes not only the implements of labour. The implements of labour constitute only part of the means necessary for production. Therefore it will be more exact to speak, not of the development of the implements of labour, but more generally of the development of the means of production, the productive forces – although it is quite certain that the most important part in this development belongs, or at least belonged tip to the present day (until important chemical industries appeared) precisely to the implements of labour. In the implements of labour man acquires new organs, as it were, which change his anatomical structure. From the time that he rose to the level of using them, he has given quite a new aspect to the history of his development. Previously, as with all the other animals, it amounted to changes in his natural organs. Since that time it has become first of all the history of the perfecting of his artificial organs, the growth of his productive forces. <<< If homo sapiens are defined as "the tool-making animal" this raises very troublesome issues, especially because of the way that Plekhanov formulates that proposition. For Plekhanov, tool making existed "as an embryo" in some other species but it became the "distinguishing feature" of humans. The implements of labour are likened by Plekhanov to "new organs". Indeed, he even says that that these instruments of labour amount to a change in the "anatomical structure" of humans. Human history, indeed human *self-realization*, then translates into the "history of perfecting his artificial organs, the growth of his productive forces." Consider the implications of the above which are expressed below as questions: 1. If the "distinguishing characteristic" of humans is the state of their tool-making and "artificial organs", then doesn't it necessarily follow that humans of our century are more "human" than humans in previous epochs in our history? 2. If the most essential criteria for how human we are is the state of our development of the forces of production, then doesn't it necessarily follow that humans in contemporary social formations in which there is a less advanced development of artificial organs are less human than humans who have access to and utilize more sophisticated artificial organs? 3. If tool-making is the "distinguishing feature" of humans, then aren't engineers, architects, machinists, and tool-makers the most human of all humans? 4. More generally, aren't skilled workers more human than unskilled workers? 5. Aren't unskilled workers who work in 'modern industry' more human than unskilled workers who work in smaller-scale industry since their artificial organs are smaller? 6. Aren't the members of the industrial reserve army less human than wage-workers since they are deprived of many of the artificial organs that wage-workers have? 7. _If_ the artificial organs associated with domestic labour are less advanced that the organs associated with workers in large-scale industry, then aren't the atomized workers who care for and nurture children and others (e.g. the elderly) in households less human? 8. [Following-up on 3.] If those with skills in tool-making are the most human of us all, then isn't a technocracy (some might say, euphemistically, a "meritocracy") the appropriate system of political governance? After all, they are more knowledgeable and more human and hence more able to make complex social decisions, right? 9. If it is not the ownership of a _skill_ but rather the ownership and control of the _artificial organ itself_ that determines how advanced we are as humans, then surely the most human of all beings must be capitalists, right? 10. Many of these "artificial organs" have been "perfected" by the state. Indeed, the state owns and controls many of those implements of labour. Aren't the representatives and functionaries of the state then the most human of us all? 11. Shouldn't we thank capital and the state for empowering us by letting us use the artificial limbs and hence become more human? ooooooooooooooooooooo In order to avoid mis-understanding, I am NOT claiming that Plekhanov drew any of these reactionary political conclusions. On the contrary, he -- like other socialists -- believed in the principles of solidarity and equality. My point is simply that there is an *inconsistency* in Plekhanov's claim: i.e. he did not think through sufficiently the implications of his perspective. I suppose that it is not surprising that Plekhanov glorified the role of industry and the development of the forces of production, especially given the relative lack of industrialization in pre-revolutionary Russia. The development of the forces of production -- the perfection of the "artificial organs" -- was seen as being a pre-condition for establishing socialist relations of production. Yet, he seems to have been unaware of how the linking of tool-making with human-ness can lead in a direction very much contrary to the principles of solidarity and equality. This might be seen as being a latent problem without practical application, but I'm not so sure about that. After all, some later Marxists (most notably, Lenin) who were inspired by Plekhanov also put forward some technocratic initiatives about how a revolutionary movement and a revolutionary society should be governed. And, of course, there was a kind of celebration and glorification of industry by the Bolsheviks (e.g. Lenin's claim that communism is the power of electricity) which gave pride of place to party officials, scientists, skilled workers, engineers, etc. over the masses who were not part of the elite. Indeed, when the NEP was founded, even Taylorism was celebrated as an organizing principle of socialist industry. Why? Well, because it would advance the forces of production, which would create the material conditions for socialism, which would eventually usher in a new period of human history (communism) in which humans would for the first time fully realize their potential as humans and hence the "pre-history" of humanity would come to a close. It is true -- as you suggest, Dogan -- that some of these perspectives can be traced back to Marx. Others have their origin with Engels or later Marxists. In solidarity, Jerry
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sun Dec 31 2006 - 00:00:04 EST