From: Jurriaan Bendien (adsl675281@TISCALI.NL)
Date: Mon Apr 02 2007 - 14:50:33 EDT
Hi Fred, You wrote: This is the only way that there can be a quantitative ?difference? between the ?value? and the ?cost price?, which is emphasized in Marx's paragraph and by Jurrian. Thank you for your comment, but I am not sure yet if I agree. Seems to me, categorically speaking: (1) that Marx theorises the operation of the law of value in capitalism in four dimensions, namely labour-time worked to produce a product, product-values, ideal product-prices (including production prices) and real product-prices actually realised. These can evolve with some degree of freedom from each other, and precisely their deviations are of critical importance in the competition process, and shape that process. You need all four dimensions to make sense of it. In my view: (2) product-values and labour-time worked to produce them are not identical expressions, because product-values do not really refer to the actual amount of labour-time (direct and indirect) required to produce the product, but to the current social average or modal average labour-time. Marx suggests that there is a differential between the enterprise labour-cost and the socially average labour-cost for the product, and that this again is of critical importance in competition. At issue with the quote is (I thought) is: (3) the difference between "potential" surplus-value and "realised" surplus-value. The former is a value, the latter is a price. Of course, the formula C+V+S can be always construed to refer either to quantities or labour-time, or product-values or product prices (real or ideal). Marx is often a bit sloppy in his expression here, and he often does not adequately distinguish between capital advanced and capital consumed (although in Cap. 3, ch 1 he does define the difference). But apart from sloppiness, the reason for combining values and prices in one equation is that he does not simply want to "make general reflections on this unity [of production and circulation]" but "to discover and present the concrete forms which grow out of the process of capital's movement considered as a whole" (p. 115). And values and prices operate in tandem here. If we say, as Marx summarises, that: "As long as its sale price is above its cost price, even if below its value, a part of the surplus-value contained in it is always realized, i.e. a profit is made" then it seems to me, we are BOTH talking about prices AND about values, and about the relationship between them (to express that quantitatively, we really require ideal prices). The "value" here can be defined either as the actual direct and indirect labour-time required to produce it by the enterprise, or as the socially average labour-cost for that type of product, or as an ideal price. I realise this can give rise to conceptual ambiguities. Marx implies (I think) that the cutting edge of competition (and consequently the ultimate dynamic of the law of value in capitalism) is to sell a product below its socially average value, yet with a profit rate higher than the average. In other words, you use less labour and material than average to produce it, enabling a profit margin higher than average, even although you still sell the product below the ruling market prices, and below the socially average product-values. Because you therefore have more sales and faster turnover, your profit margin is higher in the same accounting period. The inverse case would be an above-average (surplus-) profit made through selling "above value", based on supply or demand monopolies of some kind. But a monopoly obviously also makes possible underselling would-be competitors in the given case. The basic economic reality behind all of this, is that until the product is sold, it is uncertain how much surplus-value will be realised, although in aggregate we might say that X amount of value has been produced at a certain capital cost, and thus that only Y amount of surplus value can possibly be realised by the producers (the mass of profit realised and the surplus-value produced are at least approximately the same, which is what Marx claims to be an empirical fact - at least, no more profit can be realised from production than there exists newly created surplus-value from production, although less could contingently be realised). So there is both the potential surplus value (value concept) and the hypothetical profit (ideal price), and there is the realised surplus value and the realised profit (actual prices). But even although not all the surplus value included in the product-value of the new commodity may be realised by the producer, it is nevertheless possible that the producer may obtain an above-average profit. In this case, you simply sell more at a lower price and a lower production cost with a higher turnover, so that your profit margin is nevertheless still higher than the average. We know that there exists no perfect competition, because competition also involves blocking competitors in various ways (including protectionism, regulation etc.). But it appears to me that Marx is suggesting that in pure ("cut-throat") competition, the ultimate challenge is one of selling below value, at an above-average rate of profit, that is the basic tendency of the system. With an above-average S/V, a lower C input cost, and a higher turnover, this is in principle possible, even if you have to import from China. In this interpretation, it would be wrong to say that the mass of surplus-value is "redistributed" from a "pool" according to the capital outlays involved, although it may look like that if we decide to model a uniform (general) profit rate. It is not true, that some producers really hand over a chunk of newly produced value to other producers in the same accounting period. Instead, it is only that some enterprises realise more of the potential surplus-value as profit than others, given a ruling price-level for the product, but the extent to which they can do this, depends precisely on the prevailing value relations in society which they have to work with, and which they do not control (they can control only part of what happens, in their own enterprise). These value relations exist as objectified (objective) relationships, regardless of whether they are expressed in prices or not, simply because producing a certain type of product really incurs a certain cost in labour-time to produce. The reason why we would talk about "product-values" here at all, rather than about ideal prices, is I think that these product-values are an objectified reality, whereas ideal prices are only computational constructs used only for valuing purposes and to explain the relationships involved. If a product takes X amount of labour to produce, this is an objective fact influencing economic behaviour regardless of what anyone thinks, not an idealisation. Suppose we drop the notion of objectified value (value as objective reality) altogether, we assume value is purely subjective, and that there are only negotiated prices. In that case, John Eatwell's delightfully worded scenario applies: "Since the markets are driven by average opinion about what average opinion will be, an enormous premium is placed on any information or signals that might provide a guide to the swings in average opinion and as to how average opinion will react to changing events. These signals have to be simple and clear-cut. Sophisticated interpretations of the economic data would not provide a clear lead. So the money markets and foreign exchange markets become dominated by simple slogans--larger fiscal deficits lead to higher interest rates, an increased money supply results in higher inflation, public expenditure bad, private expenditure good--even when those slogans are persistently refuted by events. To these simplistic rules of the game there is added a demand for governments to publish their own financial targets, to show that their policy is couched within a firm financial framework. The main purpose of insisting on this government commitment to financial targeting is to aid average opinion in guessing how average opinion will expect the government to respond to changing economic circumstances and how average opinion will react when the government fails to meet its goals. So "the markets" are basically a collection of overexcited young men and women, desperate to make money by guessing what everyone else in the market will do. Many have no more claim to economic rationality than tipsters at the local racetrack and probably rather less specialist knowledge." http://www.prospect.org/print/V4/12/eatwell-j.html Of course - and this is important - Marx I think never denied value does have a subjective characteristic beyond having an objectified characteristic. In the last instance, valuing human subjects are required for value to exist at all. If we imagine a stock of products and assets existing without any people existing anywhere, not an atom of value would I think exist. Marx says specifically in this regard at the beginning of Vol. 3 that "The configurations of capital, as developed in this volume, thus approach step by step the form in which they appear on the surface of society, in the action of different capitals on one another, i.e. in competition, and in the everyday consciousness of the agents of production themselves" (Pelican edition, p. 117). In other words, the theory includes this "everyday consciousness". The fact, that objectified product-values exist regardless of the valuations of individuals, does not I think imply for Marx that value has no subjective aspect. It does, necessarily. But one aim of his theory of value is precisely to explain the consciousness people have of economic value, with reference to an objective reality that gives rise to it, and which exists, as it were, "behind the backs of the producers". The active, subjective aspect of value is emphasised by George Soros: "Every market participant is faced with the task to estimate the value in the present of a future development of events, but that development is co-determined by the value which all market participants together attribute to it in the present. That is why market participants are forced to be led partly by their subjective judgement. Characteristic of that bias is that it is not purely passive: it has influence on the course of events which it should represent. This active aspect is lacking in the concept of equilibrium such as is used in economic theory." (George Soros, "The Crisis of Global Capitalism" (1998), Chapter 3, Dutch edition, p. 83). That is correct, as far as it goes. But Marx would add, "market participants are also continuously forced to adjust their actions by objectified value relations which exist regardless of their will". In Soros's view, the reason why "market participants are forced to be led partly by their subjective judgement" is because the aggregate outcomes are in part indeterminate or unknown (they depend on what people will actually choose to do now and in the future), i.e. because "you don't know exactly what the market will do". But obviously this subjective judgement would be worth nothing at all, if it had no predictive power, if it was all one big gamble in a chaos. What Marx suggests is that the subjective judgement is not arbitrary or magical/mystical, precisely because objectified value relations exist at any time, and these enable us in principle to understand market dynamics and predict at least to some extent what will happen. Not necessarily because market actors are rational, but because they are caught up in the social rationality of capital accumulation to which they wil adjust, like it or not. The problem with equilibrium theory is that it only tells us that a price-level exists at which supply and demand will balance, and that markets tend towards this price-level. But it tells us nothing about the actual socio-economic process through which this balancing act occurs, nor is there any empirical evidence that equilibrium exists other than that prices stay constant in time or grow at proportional rates. Since prices rarely stay constant in time, and are prone to fluctuations, the amount of empirical evidence for equilibrium is very small indeed. I think that what Marx tried to do with his law of value, and associated categories, is to explain how the balancing (really, "calibrating") process actually occurs. It requires no reference to equilibrium, only to the idea that supply and demand will tend to adjust to each other; prices might stay relative constant although plenty human needs are not met. I have another job to do, so may not be able to discuss further for a few days. regards, Jurriaan
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Mon Apr 30 2007 - 00:00:16 EDT