From: Jurriaan Bendien (adsl675281@TISCALI.NL)
Date: Sat Sep 15 2007 - 10:12:41 EDT
One thing I forgot to emphasise - the "ontological status" attached to production prices (whether they are strictly theoretical (ideal) prices only in a model, or whether they are in some way derived from actual prices charged) obviously affects the question of what these prices can possibly explain. In the case of e.g. Anwar Shaikh or Makoto Itoh, the argument is clearly that production prices are strictly theoretical prices, which do not exist in reality. They function only to describe the movement of production capital in its purest form, under simplifying assumptions, at quite some distance from empirical reality. But the corrolary is that production prices cannot explain actual empirical price levels, and that, if they are said to perform a "regulative function" or describe "averages", this exists only within the context of a theoretical model. Shaikh therefore moots the concept of "regulating prices" which are prices distinct from production prices. In the case of e.g. Ernest Mandel, the production prices do have an empirical reality, i.e. they can explain real price averages, at least by specifying production constraints (an empirically given cost-structure for inputs and an empirically given price-structure for outputs). The implicit argument here is, that if production prices are only theoretical prices with no bearing on empirical reality, then what is the point of the theory? The theory is supposed to explain the facts of experience, and be disciplined by observables. If it doesn't do that, there is no point in the theory. If production prices are only theoretical prices with no reality, it would, according to this argument, be analogous to saying that in order to explain a moving object X, I have to assume that X is stationary, and that I cannot explain X, if it is a moving object, only as a stationary object. But X is in truth a moving object, not a stationary object, and therefore if I abstract from its movement, the "explanation" ignores an essential feature of what makes X what it is. In that case, we haven't really got any further than perhaps specifying "some things which you would have to explain", if you wanted to explain X. I said previously "A theoretical price cannot really be a regulating price, because it exists only in theory, and therefore it "determines" nothing about actual prices". Obviously the way some economists get around that problem, is to postulate that actual prices will trend across time towards the equilibrium price, and therefore, the equilibrium price-level can be said to exercise a real regulative function, because actual prices trend towards it. This is just another way of saying that prices, "being what they are", have the tendency to approximate the equilibrium price more closely across time, or that markets tend to move towards equilibrium. The question is then, how you know that, and how you could prove it. And basically you can prove it only by (1) devising a theory of the equilibrium price, (2) predict what the equilibrium price-level will be, and then (3) test if actual prices do tend to approximate it, across time. If it is found that actual prices do not behave in a way that equilibrium theory predicts, however, then you always have three possibilities: (a) the theory is wrong, (b) the actual price movement is an exceptional case to the rule, or (3) there is some problem in the methodology of measurement. And you may not be able to establish which it is. But such tests are anyway very rare, in part because of the difficulty of specifying what the equilibrium price-level would be (the choice of assumptions and what entitles you to those assumptions). Instead, mostly what economists do, is simply to extrapolate future prices from past prices, an extrapolation which usually has very little to do with equilibrium theory. It is just established empirically, that if certain prices go up some other prices go up, if certain prices go down, other prices go down etc. and then you can infer stochastically that a certain constellation of price-levels will tend to move in a certain direction, even quite independently of any proof in causal terms of why they happen to move in that direction. Given that therefore equilibrium theory has little explanatory power, beyond proving that an equilibrium price level "could" exist, it may be regarded as odd that Marxists should devote so much importance to it. Although this is often overlooked in the literature, Marx himself in his abstract theory of capital distributions never talked about "inputs" and "outputs", he talked about a quantity of capital which is transformed into a larger quantity of capital, in abstraction of the specific assets which that quantity of capital represents (except C, V and S, and a broad distinction between three output-defined sectors) and in abstraction of the moment of purchase or sale. What is the difference? Inputs are defined in terms of a volume of purchases during an interval, and outputs are defined in terms of a volume of sales during an interval, and the net output or value added is defined in terms of these costs less sales, by some accounting procedure involving grossing and netting. The point however that Marx makes, is that the "value" of capital advanced, capital consumed and capital earnings realised cannot be simply expressed in those terms, from a "macro-economic" point of view. Why? Because from that point of view, capital assets are in reality constantly being bought, used and sold above or below their current socially established value ("what they are really worth"). That is precisely why Marx abstracts in the way that he does. If assets are worth simply what they currently sell for (price=value), there is zero point in this procedure at all. What is the real purpose of such a theory, in which capital values and capital prices constantly deviate? I don't really think the reason is to show "how the production system reaches equilibrium, using an accounting theory". I think the reason is to explain the real economic behaviour of the agents of production, and the dynamics of the movement of capitals, i.e. to reveal the way production activities will be adjusted and developed according to the movements and valuations of capital, given that the production of output is conditional on the accumulation of capital, and the competition over that capital. You don't even need price-value deviations to devise an equilibrium theory, just inputs,outputs and prices will do. In the real world, however, management and capitalists do in fact use models making similar assumptions to Marx's models. Group controller Gerard Ruizendaal of Royal Philips Electronics said for instance that "The main idea is to improve our economic value-added every year so our return of capital is more than our cost of capital." (cited in "The value creation equation", Corporate Finance Magazine, March 2004). The main idea does not describe all they do, but it is the "main idea". Why is value theory brought into the discussion by these managers and capitalists? Ultimately, because you cannot even talk about price aggregates and price relations which constantly change without making reference to values. All accounting presupposes notions of value conserved, value destroyed, value used up, value added, and comparable value, without which you cannot analyse transactions at all. Beyond that, the accounting information is imperfect, and we still need to theorize about what it means, i.e. we have to interpret it, to know what to do. We can dispute about how these values are in fact formed, or how they specifically exist, but that you need them and do assume them, becomes perfectly obvious when you examine what people actually do, when they "work with prices", i.e. the phenomenology of prices. (As I am now at last on holiday I am taking a break from OPE-L) Jurriaan
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sun Sep 30 2007 - 00:00:05 EDT