The following is a belated response to Alan's F's post entitled: "When exactly is a good priced [Alan]" {To read his post, see: http://ricardo.ecn.wfu.edu/~cottrell/ope/archive/9511/0071.html i.e. [OPE-L:461] (first series), dated 11/09/95.} (This, of course, indicates that it's never too late to respond to a post that has been archived!) ------------------------------------ At various times, reference has been made on this list to the "law of one price" (LOOP). In the above-mentioned post, Alan discusses a number of issues. One of these concerns the creation of a "uniform price" for "similar commodities." He wrote: "Thus, once the price is fixed, by whatever means -- for example, if even one good trades at that price -- then *all* similar commodities take on that price whether or not they are sold." To begin with, Alan has confused "similar commodities" with *homogeneous commodities*. What Alan is asserting would only thus hold under other specified conditions for homogeneous commodities. If they are only "similar commodities", then there is no reason to expect that all similar commodities will have a uniform price. This is not an insignificant distinction in contemporary markets where product differentiation has meant that most commodities are "similar" but not "identical" [homogeneous]. This, of course, is related to the subject of price determination and competitive strategy in oligopolistic markets (a point that I made in the post that Alan was responding to). Note that Alan has made a strong claim above when he writes that "even if one good trades at that price -- then *all* similar commodities take on that price." Indeed, it is such a strong claim that it can be rejected if there is *only one* instance of where this is not the case. In what follows, I will assume for simplicity a homogeneous product. I will also assume competitive markets. What I will show is that the process that Alan asserts, which assumes the LOOP, can even under these circumstances be violated (i.e. distorted). Example 1: A Temporal Distortion ========================= Consider the fishing industry. Suppose that 20 boats go out fishing out of the same port on the same day for swordfish. Suppose, for simplicity, that the "catch" of each boat is the same. Alan's assertion would tell us that under these conditions, once one swordfish in this market sells for one price then all of the other fish (assuming equal weight and quality) will take on the same price -- "whether or not they are sold". Would this be the case in the scenario above? Assume that one of the 20 boats arrives back at the port and sells its catch, including the allegedly decisive "first fish", before the other boats. Under these circumstances, we would anticipate that the price for the "first fish" on the market will be greater than the price of the identical fish sold by the other sellers. This is, of course, because the first seller has a *temporary monopoly* on the sale of "fresh swordfish" in this market. Thus, in this instance, the market price is only "set" by the first seller for the period of time that monopoly persists. Once the other boats off-load their catch they will discover that the market price for their fish is *not* the market price for the first seller. In value terms one might view this as follows: the first seller sells her catch at a market price that exceeds value and thereby captures a portion of the surplus value produced by workers in other firms in this market. Thus, there is a rent-like mechanism that causes a redistribution of surplus-value. Example 2: A Spatial Distortion ======================= Suppose again that we are still referring to the fishing industry. In this instance, assume that there are 15 boats that will sell their catch at three different spatial locations. Suppose in this case that all 15 boats arrive in the same port at the exact same instance. According to Alan's perspective, once the price of any 1 of the fish is set then that will set the price for all of the same quality fish. Now assume that 2 of the markets are located 10 miles inland whereas the remaining market is just yards from the docks. I.e. there is a spatial separation of parts of the same market. We would, of course, anticipate that the market price for the seller that is yards away from the dock will be *lower* than the market price for the fish sold at the other locations. This is because the *transport cost* is greater for the commodities that are to be sold at the further locations. In this case again, we see that the price is *not* fixed for all commodities of the same type once one commodity has sold. From a value perspective, the sellers of the commodities destined for locations further away will have to expend more money capital on labour-power which takes the form of variable capital (since the workers who transport the commodity to market are productive of surplus value, i.e. transport represents a continuation of the process of production in the sphere of circulation). This means that the cost to produce the same commodity (including transport cost, i.e. C + V expended in transporting the commodity to market) will be higher. We would then anticipate that the value and market price will be higher. Again, the LOOP is violated. A related issue =========== Alan wrote elsewhere in the same post that "Once the price of a car falls, the price of all cars fall. Ditto if it rises. This is so regardless of whether the car actually sells." This also is not the case. *One* reason it is not the case is because it again ignores the spatial dimension of markets. E.g. suppose that the price of a car sells in Market A in Location V falls because of conditions particular to Location V (e.g. Location V is experiencing a recession and with it declining employment and demand). This would *not* then automatically mean that the price of the same car in Markets B - U in Locations W - Z will also fall. ----------------- One of the things that I find to be curious about Alan's position is that in many of the same places, indeed frequently the same sentences, that Marx refers to the importance of temporal variations in value and market price, he *also* refers to *spatial* variations. (I am thinking here particularly of Volume 2 of _Capital_). Thus, it would seem to me that Alan as a temporalist should also recognize the consequences of how capital exists not only in time but also in space. Relatedly, I think that spatial dimensions in political economy have been ignored by too many Marxists. As a consequence, it seems to me that we are not really engaging an entire part of the literature. That part of the literature that is not being sufficiently engaged concerns the work of Marxist *geographers*. A reflection of this sad state of affairs is that not one member of OPE-L is a geographer. This is despite an explosion of interest in recent years among *other* Marxists. The recent interest in geography by Marxists most probably can be traced back to the influence of the writings of David Harvey. Yet, there have been many other writers such as Peet (ed. _International Capitalism and Industrial Restructuring_), Sheppard & Barnes (_The Capitalist Space Economy: Geographical Analysis After Ricardo, Marx and Sraffa_) and Webber & Rigby (_The Golden Age Illusion: Rethinking Postwar Capitalism_) who have engaged the perspectives of many of those who are on this list. (For a listing of some of the other literature see the above and the section on "Further Reading" in John Carney, Ray Hudson, and Jim Lewis ed. _Regions in Crisis: New Perspectives in European Regional Theory_.) I don't think that we have returned the favor yet. Maybe we should do something about that. In Solidarity, Jerry
This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Wed May 02 2001 - 00:00:04 EDT