>Re: Fred Moseley [5569], Jerry Levy [5582] and Geert Reuten [5583]: Jerry: >>Fred argues [[5569]] that his perspective is preferable to >>VFT "because it has greater explanatory power." >>How are we to judge, though, which theory has >>greater explanatory power? Fred set's out this argument more fully in a 1997 piece (on his website). In my view, the sort of axiomatic logic that Moseley advocates there misses the role of the price system in allocating labour to different technical-material labour processes, as it misses the co-constitution of value and price that makes the form-determined (capitalist) economy what it *essentially* is. Further, his claim to greater explanatory power for LET seems to be based on a misunderstanding of the methodology underlying the value-form argument. As is usual in these debates, methodological and substantive issues interact. The crux of Moseley's argument (circa 1997) is that an 'adequate' theory of the magnitude of value added must meet certain logical requirements for independent determination of variables within an equation. The assumption is that theories (eg R&W's VFT) that do not meet the axiomatic requirements of analytical determination are incapable of determining the magnitude of surplus value. He then follows up this criticism by saying that Marx's LET is a 'plausible hypothesis, the validity of which should be evaluated on the basis of the extent to which it can explain the important phenomena of capitalism' (p.1). The reduction coefficients (required by Fred's own theory, and criticised by Reuten and Williams) can he says be assumed - 'taken as given' - since a 'scientific theory may involve the postualtion of unobservable entities' (p.3). Implicit but unaknowledged in all of this is the philosophical assumption that there is only one kind of scientific theory, only one valid form of (analytic) logic, and only one possible interpretation of Marx's value theory. The core assumption seems to be that Marxism can develop as a social science only when its central concepts are expressed as theorems and elucidated in formalist models designed to prove derived postulates via testable ('plausible') hypotheses. A corollary to this is the assumption that the methods thrown up by analytic philosophy are generally agreed upon, so constituting an appropriate critique of the alternative paradigm - in this case VFT. Certainly, Fred doesn't seem to give any credence to the possibility that alternative logical forms may constitute a scientific basis for inquiry. This is quite extraordinary, given that the whole project of value-form theory is, in essence, a refutation of the analytic process of abstraction!! What is at stake in VFT is precisely the status of abstractions in Marx's and Marxian value theory, and the different *meanings* of value that result from these conceptual alternatives. In taking the stand he does, Fred passes up the opportunity to develop any understanding of VFT. For VFT, any attempt to establish a relationship between independent and dependent variables is misplaced since what is fundamental about capitalism is that the variables of interest to Fred are inextricably interconnected - it is their unity that makes capitalism what it essentially is. i.e. in capitalism value and price are mutually constituted by exchange, the only process whereby the private, concrete-labour of individuals becomes validated as social, abstract labour. Hence there is no sense in which abstract-labour and value are independent of their monetary expression. On the contrary, abstract-labour is labour-time measured in money, where the money productivity of labour is the dominant operator. >From this perspective, an axiomatic logic is wholly inappropriate and lacks explanatory power as a theory of social value. Given the unity of value and price, Moseley's (1997) question must be rephrased: can any theory predict prices on the basis of labour-time? By itself labour - as measured in time - is not homogenous (i.e. a reductive abstraction) and can be made so only by assuming away a real problem, by definition (as Marx, in fact, did). Moreover, labour-time is not constant since labour-productivity changes over time. Since there is no adequate measure of physical productivity of labour, there is also no adequate measure of socially necessary labour time. How then does LET theory explain prices and profits as Moseley demands? Only by assuming them away - taking them as 'given'. Well, what does that takes labour-values as 'given' explain? In my view, what Fred demands cannot be done, since labour is not the "causal" element; rather causality must be attributed to the systemic essence of capitalism: i.e. to the valorisation process which establishes value as a pure quantitative (monetary) relationship between abstract labour and prices. The VFT alternative is to argue that essence is not labour-value, but the systemic form determination that gives the value dimension its monetary form. Concrete labour also does not have a value-form, but is brought under the dimension of value, and form determined as abstract-labour. The empirical work that accompanies this explanation of what capitalism is *essentially* is not therefore concerned with the verification of hypotheses about labour-values and/or their conservation in prices (what anyway are labour-values apart from their expression in prices?). Rather the concern is with an inquiry into *how* the value dimension interacts with core (non-contingent) elements as well as non-essential (contingent) elements of the system. Given the research agendas of prominent writers within the VFT tradition (eg Geert's current inquiry into business cycles) it might be legitimately argued then that VFT expands the scope for theoretical and empirical research beyond the current fixation on determination of profits by so-called labour values. Moreover, it challenges the Ricardian assumption (openly stated in Moseley's's 1997 website paper) that this is Marx's 'main' objective. One more point can be made in VFT's favour. Ultimately, the methodological imperative guiding a systematic presentation remains the determination of the object-totality. In the case of capitalism, however, the comprehension is never complete since value cannot reproduce itself as a self-sustaining totality. Fully determined, the value-form grasps neither labour-power (which takes on the value form, but isn't produced within capitalist relations of production, and so is *not* a commodity) nor money (as the sole autonomous existence of the value-form - see Mike's 1992, 1998 in CJE). Thus, VFT *verifys* Marx's crucial insight that capitalism cannot fully determine its conditions of existence. Moseley's objection to VFT - as he sets it out in his 1997 piece - fails to get to grips with any of this, since it fundamentally misses (or misrepresents) the crucial argument - the systemic causation - that determines VFT results. Now, what is the point of attacking a straw man? I think Fred's assertions provide an illuminating demonstration of a key point in this debate. That is, without agreed criteria for evaluating arguments, and without arguments to justify these criteria, there is no way to resolve points of controversy - either in discussions of Marx's theory, or in discussion of VFT reconstructions of it. Like value and price, method and substance are inextricably interconnected. comradely, Nicky ----------------------------- ---------------------------------- Nicola Mostyn (Taylor) Faculty of Economics Murdoch University Australia Telephone: 61-8-9385 1130
This archive was generated by hypermail 2b30 : Sat Jun 02 2001 - 00:00:07 EDT