From: Paul C (clyder@GN.APC.ORG)
Date: Sat Jun 05 2004 - 18:15:20 EDT
Rakesh Bhandari wrote: > > >>> >>> >>> Marx implicitly begins with the recognition that in a system of >>> general commodity exchange and production one commodity had come to >>> specialize in the function of expressing the value of all the other >>> commodities, as universal equivalent. I think Marx is interested in >>> the history of money insofar as he can lay out the "practical >>> conditions that made both necessary and possible the the >>> specialization of a certain category of commodity" in this function >>> of universal equivalent (Godelier). >> > > As I said in my last post (reproduced below), Marx begins with the > apparent: in a system of generalized commodity production, one > commodity has been selected in which all the others express their > value. He then relates the history and logic of how one commodity > came to be so selected or in other words the logic of practice that > drove humanity from the simple to the universal value form. Marx is > concerned not with transitions in forms of consciousness alone but in > the "institutional" forms of a social form, the forms of the > equivalent form. One then gives a rational account of that history, > that is an ideal genesis of the money form. Here we have a particular problematic speaking, one which allows a very selective appreciation of the reality at the time. It requires a particular theoretical perspective to see the monetary system as 'one commodity specialising in the function of universal equivalent' since empirically this is not what one perceived at the time. 1. Gold did not function as the universal measure of value in early capitalist Britain, the Pound Sterling did. 2. The Pound Sterling, was a notional unit of account recognised by the British state, commercial transactions were carried out in terms of this unit rather than in terms of units of gold, or in terms of Guineas another state unit of account. 3. The Pound Sterling had multiple representations in common use: a) Bank of England Notes. b) Bank of Scotland Notes. c) Bank notes of other commercial banks. d) Cheques drawn on these banks. e) Gold sovereigns. f) as 4 silver crowns g) as 240 copper pennies. f) Treasury tallies. 4. Even if one accepts the theoretical premise that money is a commodity, there were actually two commodities that could plausibly be taken to be the substance of money - gold and silver, since coins in both forms were issued and circulated. Therefore the premise that the universal equivalent was a single commodity was not met. 5. But to define it as a commodity one had to ignore all the non-metallic forms assumed by the Pound. 6. One also had to account for the contiued smooth functioning of the capitalist system in periods when convertibility of Bank of England notes into gold was dropped. Why should the Pound still have functioned when it no longer had any guaranteed equivalent in gold? We are of course mnuch more familiar with this sate of affairs - since it is some 70 years since the British state attempted to define Sterling the price of gold. Marx might be forgiven for seeing non-convertible currencies as an aberation whose operation was to be explained by an absent cause - the gold that would have circulated if, counter-factually, the gold standard had not been dropped. >> The problem with an ideal genesis is that it tells you more about your >> theory than it tells you about what happened. One can have an arbitrary >> number of theories from which one can construct ideal histories that >> purport to explain the present - on what basis does one then choose >> between them? > > > I don't think it's arbitrary for Marx to analyze in logical and > historical terms why the generalized commodity production came to > depend on the selection of a universal equivalent. > > He is interested in the relation between commodity and money. > > It's not clear to me what Knapp or chartalist theories of money add > to or controvert about this, but I shall read Ingaham. > I agree that generalised commodity production does require a universal scalar measure of value. This is not the same thing as saying that this scalar measure must be a commodity. > > In defetishizing money, Marx argues that money > has the power of direct exchangeability only because a system of > generalized commodity production and exchange demands a commodity be > selected in which all others express their value (we can trace this > process of selection from simple to general to universal value form, > which is both a logical and historical process; tracing the process > in this way Marx calls an ideal genesis of the money form). There seems to me to be 2 problems with this argument 1. Generalised commodity production requires a universal scalar measure of value, but this does not logically imply that that scalar must itself be a commodity. One could as well argue : value is social labour time, the Pound Sterling measures value, thus the Pound Sterling is just another name for a certain quantity of social time. 2. The logical deductive approach suffers from the Hegelian weakness of hiding its premises in order to arrive at pre-ordained conclusions. The hidden premise in Marx's argument is the archetypal bourgeois world view that commodity exchange is the prior, the state superstructure is the consequence. Thus given that he initially considers commodity exchange in the absence of the state, he is forced to conceptualise how such an abstract system could give rise to money. But this is a fetishised inversion of reality imposed by the context of Marx's work - the critique of bourgeois political economy. From a historical materialist standpoint we know that the state was the prior and commodity production came later. Thus the problem that Marx is trying to solve is a problem that is only meaningfull within the context of bourgeois political economy, for historical materialism it does not exist. > >
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Tue Jun 08 2004 - 00:00:01 EDT