From: glevy@PRATT.EDU
Date: Sat Jul 10 2004 - 13:05:41 EDT
---------------------------- Original Message ---------------------------- Subject: measurement of abstract labor From: "Jurriaan Bendien" <andromeda246@hetnet.nl> Date: Tue, July 6, 2004 5:53 pm To: "Rakesh Bhandari" <rakeshb@stanford.edu> Cc: glevy@pratt.edu -------------------------------------------------------------------------- Hi Rakesh, You wrote: "But for Marx value is in fact neither subjective nor objective, based on neither personal evaluations, however aggregated, nor on the inherent properties of things. Value is thus neither subjective nor objective; that is why we don't know where to have it. Value is a social objectivity, a new kind of objectivity, a fused category of objective idealism and physical realism." I have a somewhat longwinded reply to that. It seems odd to say that value is neither subjective nor objective. In that case, it sounds more like phlogiston or orgone. I think the only way in which this statement can make sense is to say that value is a (social) relation, but the question then is (1) what that relation is a relation between, and (2) whether that relation exists mind-independently or not, and if so, in what way. I think that Marx used the term (economic) value in numerous, differing ways (because he investigates different conditions of exchange and different conditions in which value magnitudes can vary), but basically Marx's "value" refers to a characteristic which people attribute to the products of human labor, it is an attribute of products of human labor of whatever kind. That attribute (or social construct) would not exist without people making the attribution, but the point is that the attribute exists independently of particular people, as a social fact. Consequently, (1) (economic) value, which brings products in relation with each other, presupposes the simultaneous existence of a double relationship, namely between people, and between people and their products. That relationship is objective, to the extent that it exists independently of any particular human subjects. This objectivity expresses the social and physical necessity for human co-operation as a group in an economic community, and the fact that human beings are social beings, whether they like it or not. (2) (economic) value exists prior to, and independently of exchange and prices, historically and logically. Most of the total product (past and current) of human labor available for use and consumption as property has a value, but no actual price (at best a theoretical, ideal or hypothetical price) because it isn't being traded. All price aggregation implicitly refers to, and necessarily requires, a concept of economic value. (3) (economic) value for Marx is a purely social characteristic, because it refers to a valuation made in practice by people within human society, and to which they adjust their behaviour. But if value is an "objectified" social characteristic, that is because these products really (objectively) took a definite amount of labor-time and energy to make, which normally strongly influences the ratios which products exchange (a third relationship, namely the relationship between products). This physical fact means that, whatever subjective valuations people may make, there are objective sublimates for prices and price relativities, which set limits to the range within which prices can normally move. In other words, the relationship between products is governed by the double relationship I have mentioned. Exchange-ratios are therefore also enforced by social norms, and these norms are objective. This is mostly ignored in modern economics because it tends to abstract from one-half of the double relationship, namely relations between people, and looks instead mainly at the relation between people and their products, or what is implied for this relationship by the relationship between products. It assumes that relations between people of a given type ("rational market actors") exist, but doesn't discuss or explain them - that is more a topic of other social sciences. This interpretation makes economics a technical science and "the economy" a sort of "engine". However, as soon as markets cease to be self-balancing, such that the price-relationship between products of whatever type is disturbed, then modern economics must resort to extra-economic factors to explain that problem. The advantage of Marx's theory is, that by explicitly including both sides of the double relationship involved in the existence of economic value, that those "extra-economic factors" are not "extra-economic" but are internal to economic science and explicitly theorised. But that is because "economic" for Marx does not mean simply "commercial" or "efficient trade", but refers to the allocation of human labor-time and the expenditure pattern of human energy. In addition, money as universal equivalent is an objectified means for the exchange of products, and is thus a practical means for the conservation and measurement of value in time and space, essential for regular trading practices, and consequently also a practical means for claims or entitlements to products of whatever kind. An economy characterised by a universalised market (in which everything has a price, or can have one) and dominated by the chrematistic activity of capital accumulation, accomplishes in practice the reification of labor, and makes the abstraction "just so much labor-time or so many labor hours" in general possible. Labor therefore can become treated in practice as an abstract value, which imposes social norms to which people adjust their behaviour. I take Marx's critique of political economy to be saying that the necessary result of generalised capital accumulation in a universalised market is the reification of human labor, meaning in the first instance that human labor is in practice treated as a quantifiable quality, separate and separable from human subjects performing that labor, a process facilitated by the general use of money. This is the primary sense in which Marx says that "people become dominated by the products of their own hands and brains" - the exchange relations between products of whatever kind begin to dominate and shape the social relations between people. If this reification is reflected in economics, that just means that one abstracts away from the social relations between people and delegates that to some other science. Social relations refer to relationships and interdependencies between people insofar as they belong to a social group, relations between social groups, and relations between an individual and a group. These relations and interdependencies exist objectively, because they do not depend on any particular human individuals for their existence. They exist because a human being, as a social being, is part of social groups whether he likes it or not, and these groups exists irrespective of what individuals may think or do (Marx of course argues they influence what individuals will think or do). Marx suggests that labor-as-value has, dialectically speaking, both positive and negative effects for human civilisation. On the one side, it makes possible the most detailed economising of human labor through meticulous accounting techniques, and consequently an enormous increase in productivity. On the negative side, are the phenomena of the reification, exploitation and alienation of human labor which Marx (not exhaustively) describes, because labor becomes treated in practice as an abstract quantity separate(d) from human subjects (is objectfied). Labor-as-value means that labor becomes capital, a capital value, capital in motion, variable capital, an accounting entry. Substantively the reification of labor entails the inversion of object and subject, active and passive, means and ends. Thus the human being as creative producer is forced to view his own work as a means to an external end, and producers themselves become a means to an end for which maybe they do not care much at all or which they don't even know. Work becomes "just work" as a "natural, obvious" reality without necessarily expressing anything anymore about the true nature of the person. Harry Braverman referred to this as the "degradation of labor". Total reification such as accomplished by postmodernity means that people no longer believe that they can collectively shape or reshape their own society, the society they themselves have made and re-made, i.e. they feel they have totally lost control over their communal life as citizens and maybe can express their real nature only as consumers. From Marx's own plans, it's clear that, despite important suggestions in manuscripts, his social-scientific project is radically unfinished; he didn't get round to a substantive theory of wage regulation, share-capital, landed property, the state, foreign trade, the world market, and consumption. The dogmatic ossification of his thought as "Marxism-Leninism", and the resultant fear of "unorthodox" innovation, has meant that rather few theoretical advances were made consistent with his theory. But that also means there is still plenty of creative work to do ! People who reject value theory, only do so while surreptitiously re-introducing the concept "by the back door" so to speak in their choice of price relativities which they deem relevant and important. Any careful logical analysis of what people are saying when they discuss price relationships shows that a concept of value always lurks in the background, without which it would be impossible to talk about price-relations and aggregations anyway. I like to put it this way: there are billions of actual and ideal prices; what justifies grouping particular prices and relating them to other prices ? At this point, even the learned economist Alan Greenspan, steeped in statistical knowledge, succumbs to mysticism and refers to Adam Smith's "hidden hand", noting that the system of prices "does seem to work". But obviously that is not the same as offering a coherent theory. At best, he offers a pragmatic, flexibly adjusted, empirical eclecticism, but the problem there is that almost any conclusion can follow from it. The challenge for us is to devise theory which shows that not just anything can happen and can explain why some outcomes are much more likely to happen than others. If Marx's theory has an advantage, it is that it seeks to provide an internally consistent conceptualisation of economic value rather than an eclectic one, offering the possibility of inverting the inversions to which I have referred, and reconstituting human subjects as real subjects rather than objects of capital. It is true that capital value can be measured only in labour hours or money(-prices), and the temptation is for an economist to say that, therefore, we don't need any concept of value. But as I have said, a concept of value is necessarily implied anyway, and all Marx does, is to try and make the implicit explicit, showing exchange and trading relations to be historically formed social processes. I dissent from the opinion that Marx offers no theory of prices, because I think he does: - by offering a substantive theoretical explanation of what price is, - because value relations explain relative price movements - because it provides a coherent way of explaining those movements in the sense of aggregate empirical results. Moreover, I think a theory of value is also essential to developing a view of a just and efficient allocation of labor, and of the products of that labor. Hence I think there is no way at all that the theory of value Marx sought to develop in a consistent way will easily go out of date. At most you can say that it is, as I have suggested, radically unfinished, because he just did not discuss many important topics. If you analyse what is meant by the concept of "corporate governance" it is clear that it is premised on the separation of ownership of assets, dispersed all over the globe, and the control over the productive use of those assets in situ. That creates a problem of responsibility and security, and then you have to "governance" that somehow. But as soon as managers have to implement or conform to "corporate governance", then they start talking about "value-based management" which refers to doing the things that maximise share-holder returns. All of a sudden it then turns out that "value" is an objective operative force anyway, referring to real relationships which impose themselves and cannot be ignored. In Marx's theory, utilising the concept of surplus-value (practically speaking, the net income yield on value added regardless of any particular economic source), that is of course perfectly explicable, but the point here is that in practice intelligent managers do not get away from using the concept of value either, even if they have their heads stamped full of neo-classical economics which says value is "just whatever somebody's subjectively prepared to pay for a good or service". In the real world, "the market" doesn't simply offer freedom to buy and sell, it also compels sale and purchase. It's precisely this necessity to buy and sell which makes an economic science possible. I think it's best though to say Marx did not have the last word to say about the theory of economic value - see e.g. the works of Mauss, Gersh, Uno, Graeber, Malinowski and so on. Regards Jurriaan
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sun Jul 11 2004 - 00:00:01 EDT