From: glevy@PRATT.EDU
Date: Sun Apr 09 2006 - 14:40:56 EDT
Paul B asked recently for literature on Marx and calculus. Here's a recent paper from Denmark on that subject. Is there anybody on the list, with a greater knowledge of calculus than I, who can comment on the following? In struggling with differential calculus, was Marx struggling with how to present his theory in a more dynamic form? In solidarity, Jerry <http://home20.inet.tele.dk/swing/Hegel_Marx_and_the_Differential_Calculus.htm> ------------------------------------------------------ An essay about HEGEL, MARX AND THE DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS Raymond Swing, Copenhagen (Swing@mail.tele.dk) This paper discusses aspects of H.–H. v. Borzeszkowski’s and R. Wahsner’s paper Infinitesimalkalkül und neuzeitlicher Bewegungsbegriff oder Prozess als Größe (Jahrbuch für Hegelforschung 2002) but first it presents its author’s general view on the calculus and the limes transition thereby underscoring the importance of comparability and steadiness of all involved parameters and the real number system as well as of the importance of subjective moments like anticipation and decision for all handling things and to define identity and continuity. On this basis the author shows that one main difference between Hegel and Newton is their different relation to time as independent variable. Thus Hegel attempts no ‘dynamisation’ of his social philosophy but rather recognises a ‘process as magnitude’ as a specific systemic property of the young capitalist society at his time. Marx in this respect in his Mathematical manuscripts and Capital partly follows Hegel, even if he underscores the importance of time as an essential factor of his value concept. In a couple of books and essays Horst-Heino v. Borzeszkowski in cowork with Renate Wahsner have discussed among other things G. W. F. Hegel’s philosophical reflections upon physics and the differential calculus as developed for functional analysis by Newton and Leibniz. Hegel in his second edition of Wissenschaft der Logik. Teil I. Die objektive Logik. Erster Band. Die Lehre vom Sein (1832) was especially concerned with this issue and its supposed philosophical implications – and asserted insufficiencies. These Hegelian reflections have been analysed by Borzeszkowski and Wahsner in a recent paper Infinitesimalkalkül und neuzeitlicher Bewegungsbegriff oder Prozess als Größe (Preprint no. 165 from the Max Planck Institute for the History of Sciences, 2001, also published in Jahrbuch für Hegelforschung 2002). It is obvious that the ‘Modern Concept of Movement’ as well as the notion ‘Process as Magnitude’ mentioned in this title are central issue also to the present work. It could therefore be of some interest to see how their common comments on the Hegelian view relates to the ideas presented here and so to make more clear also the relation between this one and other more general philosophical problems and their history. Resuming my own ideas about the philosophical content of the differential calculus in the light of Hegel’s notion of movement as the ‘existing contradiction’ (‘daseiender Widerspruch’) could perhaps most shortly be done as follows. Let us take our starting point in the two spatial locations of a moving body x and x’, or x and x + Dx. The second location x’ must somehow relate to the first one to express a realised movement or process, that is, simply the (continuous) change from being at the location x to the other location x’. So these two spatial determinations in the sense of ‘locations’, places, or more generally, ‘states’, are different but nevertheless in some formal sense ‘equal’ (comparable). When x is recognised to be the case we naturally anticipate x’ and we write the above used anticipation notation <x|x’>. To be able to make such anticipations is the general condition for all the following arguments. So from the normal (‘scientific’) third-person stance to ‘confirm’ x is the condition even for knowing the real (substantiated, persisting) object of analysis as such, further of its being in (occupying) x and that (‘actualised’) it later will be in the new location (‘state’) x’, thereby just ‘having’ that changed location or ‘state’ as a variable property; or, in another wording, ‘having’ the property of (spatially) being changing (moving). Anticipation, in fact, is the real problem of the Hegelian ‘Existing Contradiction’ contained in the ‘movement’ x ® x + Dx. Anticipation is always being realised in ‘real (subjective) time’ of NOW and THEN. However, such notions are neither expressible in mathematical nor physical terms and therefore most often stay implicit. This temporal moment, therefore, ‘time’ as such, had itself to be substantiated and conceptualised, which for the first time was realised by Galileo by using ‘time’ as the independent variable in his equations. However, the real ‘independence’ here was – again implicitly – realised by the active physicist himself deciding to make his experimental operations and measurements at certain ‘timepoints’ or NOWs, say, exactly at the instants of time t0 and t0 + Dt (t and t’). In this way – and only in this way – the ‘movement’ x0 ® x0 + Dx could immediately be related to ‘time’, the ‘flow’ of which, so to say, itself makes the ‘movement’ t0 ® t0 + Dt. These instants, then, were indicated by means of clocks readings, so that the simultaneous movements of body and hands over the dial could be immediately compared and numerically indicated by their coordinates and angles, respectively; so the movement (process) and its ‘velocity’ could in the registered time interval (in the average) be expressed by the mathematical different quotient Dx/Dt. However, to measure or mediate (model) such magnitudes in numerical it was necessary, first, that the number system itself ‘resembled’ (was isomorphic to) both spatial distances and time durations so that these (the measured magnitudes) could be related to each other in the mentioned proportion. But all this was in no way given. In the last instance this was the problem of continuity. On the other hand, to go further to indicate also velocity at a singe timepoint or at a single spatial coordinatepoint it was necessary that the development of the number system had advanced to include also irrational numbers (real number system) making calculation of infinite number series possible, which was first achieved in the course of the nineteenth century. This was needed for any exact operation with infinitesimals and, consequently, to give a strict mathematical definition of the limit. The recognition of an instantaneous change of the (material or mathematical) function ¦ at the decided NOW could then be defined by the limes transition of the differrence quotientDx/Dt into the differential quotient dx/dt, Dx/Dt ® dx/dt. These magnitudes x (and Dx or the infinitesimal dx) and t (and the corresponding Dt or dt) had always to be expressed through concrete numbers, i.e., by the unity of qualities and quantities; thus Dx/Dt and dx/dt could never be viewed as ‘pure’ mathematical expressions but would always be associated to some physical concepts, for instance as here to the conceptualised relationship between distance and duration. However, the fact in this connection is that calculating the differential quotient we from the outset must have a theory or at least some elementary knowledge about the ‘movement’ or change in question represented by the function ¦; if not, we would not be able to anticipate anything at all. We also had to suspect that this function or process ¦ could represent by just that instantaneously measurable (respectively calculable) ‘quality’ at the ‘timepoint’ t0; missing such a knowledge, we would not even have looked for it! On this basis, eventually, we can write the equation in question referring to all corresponding concepts ¦0, x0, and t0: ¦0 = dx/dt, ¦0 just being the velocity in x0 at the time t0. As a consequence, not only the body’s existence as such, also its location and an essential property (the faculty of moving) has been defined as different aspects of its ‘state’. It is this generalised ‘state’ that troubles Hegel. What Hegel and others have characterised as the ‘existing contradiction’, this ‘contradiction’ between being in a state, for example, of a certain location and, at the same time, being not in that ‘state’ but in a ‘state of change’, of movement or processing, is at issue here. The second aspect of ‘being in change’ could be viewed as a measurable process itself, which inspired Hegel to talk of a ‘process as magnitude (‘Prozess als Größe’) based on some ‘science of magnitude’. In this sense this process appears as a kind of bodyinherent power (cf. the old notion of ‘Impetus’), which even Marx in his Matehematical manuscripts referred to as an operative principle with dx as its symbol (see below). Now let us turn to the two essential problems to Hegel’s understanding of the differential calculus discussed by Borzeszkowski & Wahsner. The first one is that of the limes transition with its narrowing of Dx, Dy, Dt, etc. to the corresponding differentials dx, dy, dt, etc. disappearing in the limit and so at last, quantitatively, may be posited = 0. The first condition for the numerical representation the magnitudes in question was that of steadiness of the real number system had to be proven to give the concept of limit its exact definition. This indeed problematic condition for any numerical representation of physical processes, for instance a spatial movement along a certain path, was to assure that all involved developments in questions in themselves could be asserted ‘steady’ (isomorphic). This, however, is not at all a matter of course; ‘random walk’, for example, is not differentiable. The calculus always depended on the concept of steadiness valid as well to the number system, to lines in space (or other trajectories of development) as also to the ‘time line’ (consequently been conceptualised as linear parameter). On the other hand, in real physical work the exact limes transition Dx ® dx (quasi = 0) is not possible at all. The practical problem is, of course, to prepare the limes transitions of their proportion Dy/Dx ® dy/dx, as Hegel wrote, by determining the quantities in question with reasonable exactness. Every measurement is in the last instance based on identity between the value of the magnitude measured and that of the magnitude indicated by the measuring device (meter rule, balance, clock, etc.). But, how to assess that identity? And even, how at all to define identity as such as a theoretical concept? Marx offered in the first chapter of his Capital an interesting commodity or value form analysis (cf. for example, chapter XI). Here a weaver meets the tailor wanting to give some linen in reward for a new coat (value form I). Most essentially, none of them must feel cheated. So they bargain and come to the result, 20 yards of linen in regard for the coat is not too much (to the weaver) and not too little (to the tailor). So the goods themselves are thereby asserted ‘equivalent’ and the exchange can be realised. In more elaborated terms we may say that the ‘value’ of 20 yards than the ‘value’ of the coat and, at the same time, than that of the coat: LC & LC. Under this – certainly subjective – condition the two persons accept their commodities to be in respect of their ‘value’ identical (this identity definition is more thoroughly elaborated in the relevant parts of the present work). On the abstract market to accept this is the real condition for breaking off further bargaining; after all both only want to exchange their goods! What does this mean to measurements in general? Using our rules and other measureing devices we really never will be able to assess exact equality, not even a single value identity. We only assess that under the given conditions of observation we must be satisfied when the object is experienced to be neither greater (higher, heavier, etc.) than the notches of the rule or the hand of other devices indicate, nor, at the same time, to be smaller, etc. But that means that we have to make the (in itself essential but not unproblematic, dialectical) predicationas the result of the comparison process. This ideally defines identity by posited exclusion of uncertainties. Under modern measurement conditions, indeed, such uncertainties can be made small; but ‘identity’ as such will forever be an abstract concept, an ideal construct, useful and fertile for the mathematical sciences, but never found in the real world. So the problem of the disappearing infinitesimals in the infinite limit will always be problematic to the empirical sciences; and so it was, too, to the philosophers. Hegel reacts against the empirical uncertainty caused by the necessary actions and valuations made by the scientist and he does not conceptualise the necessary subjective moment of real participation inherent in the experimental sciences (contrary to the theorising afterwards!) where ‘participation’ under the first-person aspect is exactly the dialectic opposite to the concept of dominum (basic to all ‘alienation, ‘isolation’, etc.) equally essential to society in general and to science in particular treating all relevant issues under the third-person aspect. Both moments are indispensable for determining functions of things; without forms of ‘objectifying’ on the basis of constant participation in the processes to be studied (cf. Bohr and the ‘problems’ of modern quantum physics); not even such (seemingly so simple) concepts like motion and change in general can be conceptualised. Indeed, the ‘existing contradiction’ also implies the paradox that all ‘objective’ observation is realised by self-conscious scientists synchronically uniting both first- and third-person perspectives. The second problem raised by Hegel and mentioned by Borzeszkowski & Wahsner is that of the missing concept of the independent variable. The problem is here that the term dy/dx is taken as a simple proportion, not as a term in an equation, that is, not explicitly naming a process being at work. “He (Hegel) reads this expression not as ‘dy after dx’, that is, not as the changing of the magnitude y with x, not as the change of the dependent variable with regard to the independent variable of a structure defined through the function ¦ in case” (p. 10). This means that in the view of Hegel the changing magnitude of y is not seen under the condition of a (possibly provoked) change of another variable x (measured under certain conditions, for instance at a decided instant of time or a short duration of observation). Thus Hegel had no longer to do only with ‘pure’ proportions but merely recognised the practical usefulness of the calculus to the scientists. Therefore he also declares: “I eliminate here those determinations which belong to the idea of motion and velocity … because in them the thought does not appear in its proper abstraction but as a concrete and mixed with nonessential forms. “ (Hegel, p. 255) And he concludes that use of the differential calculus in relation to “the elementary equations of motion” (Hegel, p. 294) as such is without any real philosophical interest. Seen in the perspective of Hegel was at issue not so much the breaking off the infinite number series refusing exactness (absolute identification) of the measurements but rather proposed these members of the number series not “be regarded as parts of a sum, but rather as qualitative moments of a whole determined by the concept.” (Hegel, p. 264) According to him, therefore, the notion of limit was developed on the basis of a mere qualitative relation, dx and dy themselves viewed only as the moments of this so that the composed term dy/dx could be read as a single sign naming a thereby specified quality, a certain property of a thing or phenomenon as such. On this basis, of course, the quality at issue could be made subject to a ‘science of magnitudes’ to be measured under the given conditions. The essential point of ‘dynamising’ the world picture through the new temporal concepts of movement, change, function, process, etc. can as mentioned above only be understood on the historical basis of the most essential material conditions for the common life in that era always having vital (but different) meaning to the societies in question. These concepts, therefore, are (often implicitly) to be recognised as reflections on the social work, for instance in the manufactures, later on in the factories. In this perspective, in fact, capitalist factories just realise a certain new ‘quality’ represented by the economic proportion between the magnitudes of money investments (capital) and its outcome (surplus value, eventually as profit). However, more essential than this difference in their proportion, so that the proportion dy/dx can be read as the productivity measured at some certain point of time. Indeed, capitalists are primarily not interested in real (material and ideal) processes causing this productivity, only in this single proportion as such. In this sense Hegel, more or less implicitly, understood what subliminally was developing in the years about 1830 and which became rather obvious shortly after his own lifetime, just in the time of Marx. So Hegel could not yet see the need for going behind this mere proportion-thinking of his ‘science of magnitude’ just being a ‘science of value’ (the specific capitalist science of money). In this view his term dy/dx not at all aimed at any dynamism but merely stated a certain proportionality of economical values as a specific quality or property of these values as such. In this sense Hegel expresses an essential difference between the ideas of philosophers and physicists. This difference was caused by the simple fact that the physicists had an other job to do than the philosophers and economists; they were just the persons preparing this capitalist development creating the necessary ‘scientific’ technology. So they had to conceptualise the material processes underlying these economical proportions that to them were without special interest. Marx too analysed the developing social system but explicitly reflected the real (quasi-organismic) functioning of capital as an economic whole and so also had to reflect the real work (labour) to be done by the workers. So also he in his Mathematical Manuscripts is concerned with dx (in this connection, in fact, dy) that he (atemporally) characterises as an ‘operational symbol’ referring to a ‘process which must be carried out...’ (cf. Marx 1983, p. 21). Not even Marx is yet able to operate with the temporal differential quotient dx/dt even if he in his value theory explicitly includes time as the essential factor of real labour. Conceptualising of real organismic wholes was eventually made explicit by Robert Rosen by his relational analyses proposing a minimal organismic structure. On this analysis the more elaborated concepts of anticipation, circularity, complex time, etc. could be grounded, thereby explicitly conceptualising the very notion of ‘subjectivity’ (as the dialectic opposite to ‘objectivity’). Indeed, Marx came rather near – nearer than Hegel – to transgress the ideological limits of the ‘exact sciences’ to explicate the true character of real ‘becoming’ – including just notions like productivity, creativity, even of life itself. Exactly such notions are more extensively to be analysed in the time to come and will then surely cause of new mathematical, natural scientific, and philosophical problems to emerge calling for new arguments in a presumably much wider field of inquiry than the classical problems of ‘dynamisation’ of the old world picture could evoke. Literature: von Borzeszkowski, H.-H. and Wahsner, R. (2002): Infinitesimalkalkül und neuzeitlicher Bewegungsbegriff oder Prozess als Größe. Jahrbuch für Hegelforschung. (Also as Preprint no. 165 from the Max Planck Institute for the History of Sciences, 2001.) Hegel’s Science of Logic (1969). Translated by A.V. Miller, foreword by prof. J. N. Findlay. Humanities Press International, INC., Atlantic Highlands, NJ. Marx, Karl (1983): Mathematical Manuscripts of Karl Marx. New Park Publications Ltd. ¾ (1990): Capital, Vol. I , transl. by Ben Fowkes, Penguin Books (Penguin Classics). Rosen, Robert (1991): Life Itself. A Comprehensive Inquiry Into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of Life (Columbia University Press, New York)
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sun Apr 30 2006 - 00:00:06 EDT