From: Anders Ekeland (anders.ekeland@ONLINE.NO)
Date: Mon Mar 12 2007 - 03:28:28 EDT
Hi, this is a vast topic - let me just throw in a few cents: - first of all: the capitalist system is *never* in equilibrium. I am deeply sceptical (as f.ex. the historian of Austrian Ec. thought Rothbard) about the usefulness of studying equilibrium states, "natural long run prices". This goes not only for Arrow-Debreu, but also for Smith and Ricardo. Long run equilibrium prices is a contradicto in adjectivo = impossible under capitalism. - That the classics (Smith, Ricardo, Marx) had a fundamentally different - and dynamic model of capitalism is clear, but on can discuss if Marx was successful in "proving" his dynamic mental model, his main results in a static framework (= the transformation problem as conventionally defined). - Or to put it another way: Why is most economics obsessed by studying perfect stagnation? (the real name of perfect competition or long run equilibrium) - when it is growth (= increasing welfare) that is clearly the nest interesting aspect of capitalism. Economics is not about use of efficient and/or fair distribution of scarce resources - it's all about how to overcome scarce ties - in the final end - creating abundance. Accumulate, accumulate - M-C-M' that's Moses and the prophets - not static equilibrium. - The first conclusion is: No result from a static model ("Marxian", Sraffian or neo-classical) can be accepted before it is shown that it also holds in a dynamic setting, i.e. where producers can set/change prices and technology. Despite serious attempts - the major results (efficiency, Pareto-optimality etc. do *not* hold in a dynamic setting, cf. Franklin M. Fisher "The disequilibrium foundations of equilibrium economics", or Currie and Steedman "Wrestling with time". - The fact is that perfect competition is no competition at all. The most reasonable interpretation of Arrow-Debreu (or Sraffa) is a fully monopolized (one producer of each good) in a total stagnant state. That's certainly not a very attractive state, no "first best" at all. Almost any non-equilibrium, labour productivity enhancing "fifth best" is to be preferred to this state. (Cf. the Solow growth model, without change in technology.) - The fundamental point is that the same forces that drives towards equalisation of profit rates - also creates disequilibrium. Firms are forced to innovate in order to protect themselves against a situation where they compete by producing homogenous goods with the same technology to a given price. (Cf. Baumol's "The free market innovation machine" 2002 for a non-Marxian (but Marx inspired) description of this process. From the perspective of Marxian economics a dynamic model would be able to handle: - different and changing technologies - with increasing returns to scale - where *demand* determines the SNLT - where there are conflicting plans, not all plans get realised and consequently learning, change of strategies - where there is *waste*, that is labour time not being recognized as socially necessary - modelled explicitly, that is bankruptcies etc. In short - a dynamic model must not be an "Harmonilehre", that is a model of imaginary harmonious state, but to show how the incomes of the rich is actually based on the exploitation of other peoples work - out of a non-existent equilibrium, to quantify the amount of waste in order to show that a planned economy would be more rational and efficient (and "just" and "fair"). A dynamic model would show *all* the transformations ("averaging") from the private labour of each specific instance of each specific product until (labour)value is "frozen", socially accepted in the form of a market price. A dynamic will be able to visualize the why the "simple" LTV model is the best predictor of market prices and is true in this sense (= grasping the essential), but that the simple LTV model is to simple since it does not model technological change, does not model the tension, the fight over the surplus. It follows from this, that market prices are more real - and just as important as "prices of production". Market prices have no inferior status. A dynamic model would treat money - not as a commodity money - or a commodity numeraire shares, but as the expression (a complex one) of value. Money (and shares, bonds, debt, derivates, interest etc.) would be seen as part of a "control" system that creates "order out of disorder", i.e. socializes the individual labour, regulates the conflicting claims to the goods and services produced (now and future). Only in a dynamic model can you model business cycles, i.e. the macro results of weakly coordinated micro behaviour. A lot more could be said about this, but the important point is to realize that static equilibrium models are very uninteresting for the study of real capitalism. The "new solution" and even TSSI is still too "static", or to "un-dialectic" - although on the right track. But a Marxian model without technological change is not the final Marxian model. Innovation = competition and competition = innovation, and innovation is *the* most important aspect of capitalism. From a revolutionary point of view, the fact that capitalism revolutionizes the productive forces more - and order of magnitude more - than any know social mode of production - creates an enormous potential for reformist policies - so a dynamic view of capitalism also has implications for left-wing policies. Neo-classical equilibrium theory is an ideology, not a scientific theory. Sraffian and linear algebra Marxist models are very partial models. Their main use has been ideological - against dynamic economic theory. Economics will not become a science before equilibrium states are seen as rather uninteresting special cases. When that happens economics will (again) find it's place among the other social sciences since they mainly are dynamic (that is have learning, feed-back mechanisms, non-linearity) etc. The core of "Economics imperialism" is the use of static equilibrium models. When Jurriaan writes: Wouldn't it be simpler to study the real history of capitalism using the human brain as processor? Of course, but I think that simulation has a role to play. But the important thing is the kind of results you get. For example that a compressed wage scale drives innovation drives welfare - and is more efficient in creating growth than huge wage differences. But the point here is to have a dynamic mental model to study a highly dynamic system (capitalism). Let me end with an a quote from Haavelmo on Keynes: ... In reality he [Keynes] came close to building a separate theory for employment and investment, but since he in contrast to Wicksell did not build an explicit dynamic theory, he was always in a logically dangerous zone, and that created a lot of confusion. (from "The Keynesian revolution", 1977, Memorandum from the Institute of Economics, Oslo, in Norwegian.) ... a lot of confusion is what characterizes economics since almost 99% of economists try to use static concepts to grasp a dynamic reality. Regards Anders Ekeland At 00:00 11.03.2007, you wrote: >What intrigues me is Ian Wright's and Anders Ekeland's references to >"dynamic modelling" of the relationship between prices, values and >labour-time worked. > >What would the dynamic model prove, exactly? > >If I read Ian correctly, the model would prove that, under the assumption of >specified "purely capitalist conditions", a robust quantitative relationship >exists such that not only will (i) market prices of products trend towards >profit-equalising prices of production for those products, but also that >(ii) those prices of production themselves are regulated, as Marx says, by >current product-values which are (iii) constrained by, but not identical to, >quantities of labour-time worked to produce those products (note 1: this is >a different operation from the transformation of direct prices into prices >of production; note 2: current product-values refer to current quantities of >SNLT and not historical quantities of SNLT). > >The proof would take the form that, if the qualitative and quantitative >assumptions of the model are accepted, then this logically entails the >stated quantitative relationship. > >I think such a quantitative description is in principle possible to devise - >for simplicity we need not even refer necessarily to values, but just talk >only of prices and labour-hours - but even so the list of variables and >relationships necessary to specify the purely capitalist conditions >realistically is large. It exceeds by far anything we could empirically >verify from available social statistics. > >Wouldn't it be simpler to study the real history of capitalism using the >human brain as processor? > >The suggestion seems to be that the mentioned quantitative proof would make >the theory more rigorous. But what if the pure model is only weakly >reflected in verifiable reality? In that case, we would, in addition to the >large number of variables we already have in the pure model, have to >introduce all kinds of new qualifications to better approximate reality. > >But isn't it a scientific norm that the simplest theory with the greatest >explanatory power is the best theory? > >The Arrow-Debreu type model states roughly that a set of prices can always >be found at which supply and demand will balance, for all traded goods in >the economy, if we define competition, demand and prices in a certain way. >The objection to that model is that its assumptions are insufficiently >realistic, and imply a near-tautology such that if all obstacles to trade >are removed, one will be able to trade all goods. But a similar type of >objection could be made against the suggested Marxian model of pure >capitalism based on a general rate of profit. > >In Kozo Uno's view, it was sufficient to state the principles of political >economy for pure capitalism, and develop more specific theories at lower >levels of abstraction. The objection against this approach is that it is >unclear how the pure theory abstracted from history is to be concretised >consistently, and that Uno's pure capitalism is strangely a capitalism >without any consumption or a political state. It is more a Weberian ideal >type (Uno studied with Weber). > >What is preferable, a Weberian ideal type such as Marxists in reality use >despite their odes to "dialectics" and suchlike, or a computational model >based on counterfactual (oversimplified) assumptions? What kind of theory is >really fruitful, and how is it best formed? > >Jurriaan >
This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sat Mar 31 2007 - 01:00:12 EDT