search the site using Google™
|
|
Tracey Maclin, The Central Meaning of the Fourth
Amendment, 35 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 197 (1993).
Student Review:
In this article, Maclin points to the problem raised by the
Fourth Amendment. On one hand, the Fourth Amendment protects every
individual's right to be free from government intrusion. And yet, those
who bring Fourth Amendment claims are often criminals. Currently, the
Supreme Court interprets the central meaning of the Fourth Amendment as
reasonableness. As long as police act reasonably in search and
seizures, the Fourth Amendment is satisfied. The Court has used the
language and the history of the Fourth Amendment to establish that
warrants are not needed for every search and seizure. Maclin discusses
both the text and historical background of the Fourth Amendment in order
to question the Court's current model, and finds that rather than reasonableness, the central meaning of the Fourth Amendment is
distrust of police power and discretion.
One side of the debate on the Fourth Amendment sees the amendment
as having two separate clauses. The Reasonableness Clause protects
against unreasonable searches and seizures, and the Warrant Clause
specifies how warrants shall be issued. This rational basis model of
the Fourth Amendment maintains that a warrant is not required to protect
against unreasonable searches. This model, supported by Chief Justice
Rehnquist, is currently the dominating model of the Supreme Court. On
the other side, those who read the Fourth Amendment as establishing a
warrant preference rule contend that the Warrant Clause is tied to the
first clause, and a valid warrant is needed to protect against
unreasonable searches.
Although much current analysis has linked the text and the history
of the Fourth Amendment to the rational basis model, Maclin reexamines
these avenues to demonstrate that this conclusion is not authoritative.
First, Maclin looks at the text of the amendment and demonstrates that
the precise language of the Fourth Amendment was not a critical
consideration for the founders. A last minute change to the amendment
escaped the notice of both Congress and the state conventions.
Furthermore, a reliance on the common law of the founders is also
misguided, since the founders opposed the tenets of English common law.
Maclin next discusses the claim that the framers of the
Constitution were not concerned with warrantless searches, but rather
broad searches with unspecific warrants. Maclin mentions that before
the concern over ex officio searches (broad warrants for searches
without specific cause), the colonists also resisted warrantless
searches by British custom officers culminating in the Writs of
Assistance Case of 1761. Thus, Maclin asserts that colonists were not
unconcerned about warrantless searches. Scholars also assert that the
colonist viewed judges and warrants as oppressive forces. Maclin points
out that many state courts refused to issue writs of assistance,
demonstrating that not all judges aided in expanding the search powers
of government officials.
Instead of relying on narrow interpretations of history and the
text of the Fourth Amendment, Maclin asserts that the Court should
realize the principle behind the Fourth Amendment is a distrust of
police power and discretion. Maclin analyzes how the Court's current
rational basis model that allows warrantless searches of closed
containers values police power more than personal privacy. Rather than
allowing broad discretion to police decisions, the Court should allow
Fourth Amendment claims the same critical judicial review as other
constitutional provisions. The beginning step to using the court to
correctly analyze police intrusions is recognizing that distrust of
police power is the central meaning of the Fourth Amendment.
Article Summary by: Corrie Noir
Wake Forest University School of Law 1999
|